Knowledge

Categorical imperative

Source đź“ť

1165:
But his maxim is this: from self-love I make as my principle to shorten my life when its continued duration threatens more evil than it promises satisfaction. There only remains the question as to whether this principle of self-love can become a universal law of nature. One sees at once a contradiction in a system of nature whose law would destroy life by means of the very same feeling that acts so as to stimulate the furtherance of life, and hence there could be no existence as a system of nature. Therefore, such a maxim cannot possibly hold as a universal law of nature and is, consequently, wholly opposed to the supreme principle of all duty.
918:
such, unlike perfect duties, you do not attract blame should you not complete an imperfect duty but you shall receive praise for it should you complete it, as you have gone beyond the basic duties and taken duty upon yourself. Imperfect duties are circumstantial, meaning simply that you could not reasonably exist in a constant state of performing that duty. This is what truly differentiates between perfect and imperfect duties, because imperfect duties are those duties that are never truly completed. A particular example provided by Kant is the imperfect duty to cultivate one's own talents.
1313:
hit them." It is also a hypothetical imperative in the sense that it can be formulated, "If you want X done to you, then do X to others." Kant feared that the hypothetical clause, "if you want X done to you," remains open to dispute. In fact, he famously criticized it for not being sensitive to differences of situation, noting that a prisoner duly convicted of a crime could appeal to the golden rule while asking the judge to release him, pointing out that the judge would not want anyone else to send him to prison, so he should not do so to others.
1129:(and thus contradicts perfect duty). With lying, it would logically contradict the reliability of language. If it were universally acceptable to lie, then no one would believe anyone and all truths would be assumed to be lies. In each case, the proposed action becomes inconceivable in a world where the maxim exists as law. In a world where no one would lend money, seeking to borrow money in the manner originally imagined is inconceivable. In a world where no one trusts one another, the same is true about manipulative lies. 144: 1403:
environmental life supporting features, species dependent means of child rearing. These conditions are already rooted in mutual interdependence which makes that life form possible at all to be in a state of coordination with other forms of life – be it with pure practical reason or not. It may be that the categorical imperative is indeed biased in that it is life promoting and in part promotes the positive freedom for rational beings to pursue freely the setting of their own ends (read choices).
1184:
that a society could subsist if everyone did nothing, he notes that the man would have no pleasures to enjoy, for if everyone let their talents go to waste, there would be no one to create luxuries that created this theoretical situation in the first place. Not only that, but cultivating one's talents is a duty to oneself. Thus, it is not willed to make laziness universal, and a rational being has imperfect duty to cultivate its talents. Kant concludes in the
22: 1061:, Kant goes on to formulate the categorical imperative in a number of ways following the first three; however, because Kant himself claims that there are only three principles, little attention has been given to these other formulations. Moreover, they are often easily assimilated to the first three formulations, as Kant takes himself to be explicitly summarizing these earlier principles. 681:(Wille). The will is therefore the faculty of desire considered not so much in relation to action (as choice is) but rather in relation to the ground determining choice in action. The will itself, strictly speaking, has no determining ground; insofar as it can determine choice, it is instead practical reason itself. Insofar as reason can determine the faculty of desire as such, not only 2170: 419: 1290:, the rule prescribes: "Do not impose on others what you do not wish for yourself." In its positive form, the rule states: "Treat others how you wish to be treated." Due to this similarity, some have thought the two are identical. William P. Alston and Richard B. Brandt, in their introduction to Kant, stated, "His view about when an action is right is rather similar to the 1419:
beings who are able to exercise this purely formal reason would see. The full community of other rational members – even if this 'Kingdom of Ends' is not yet actualized and whether or not we ever live to see it – is thus a kind of 'infinite game' that seeks to held in view by all beings able to participate and choose the 'highest use of reason' (see
1439:'s self-administered blows to his own bottom were vigorous. ... Now if a man is never even once willing in his lifetime to act so decisively that can get hold of him, well, then it happens, then the man is allowed to live on in self-complacent illusion and make-believe and experimentation, but this also means: utterly without grace. 1294:; he says, roughly, that an act is right if and only if its agent is prepared to have that kind of action made universal practice or a 'law of nature.' Thus, for instance, Kant says it is right for a person to lie if and only if he is prepared to have everyone lie in similar circumstances, including those in which 1999:"This is indeed the well-known “Golden Rule” that we find in the teachings of Moses, and Confucius, and Jesus, and many others. I think, however, that all three of them would say that the most universal moral rule is even more universal than this one: something like "Do good and not evil." Kreeft, Peter (2009). 1359:
Kant denied that such an inference indicates any weakness in his premises: not lying to the murderer is required because moral actions do not derive their worth from the expected consequences. He claimed that because lying to the murderer would treat him as a mere means to another end, the lie denies
1227:
by arguing that such cruelty is a violation of a duty in relation to oneself. According to Kant, man has the imperfect duty to strengthen the feeling of compassion, since this feeling promotes morality in relation to other human beings. However, cruelty to animals deadens the feeling of compassion in
1213:
But even though it is possible that a universal law of nature could subsist in accordance with that maxim, still it is impossible to will that such a principle should hold everywhere as a law of nature. For a will that resolved in this way would contradict itself, inasmuch as cases might often arise
1183:
on the subject of "failing to cultivate one's talents." He proposes a man who if he cultivated his talents could bring many goods, but he has everything he wants and would prefer to enjoy the pleasures of life instead. The man asks himself how the universality of such a thing works. While Kant agrees
1164:
A man reduced to despair by a series of misfortunes feels sick of life, but is still so far in possession of his reason that he can ask himself whether taking his own life would not be contrary to his duty to himself. Now he asks whether the maxim of his action could become a universal law of nature.
668:
The faculty of desire in accordance with concepts, in-so-far as the ground determining it to action lies within itself and not in its object, is called a faculty to "do or to refrain from doing as one pleases". Insofar as it is joined with one's consciousness of the ability to bring about its object
1402:
and egotistical, not categorical. However, Schopenhauer's criticism (as cited here) presents a weak case for linking egoism to Kant's formulations of the categorical imperative. By definition any form of sentient, organic life is interdependent and emergent with the organic and inorganic properties,
1006:
conditions: that there be certain ends in themselves, namely rational beings as such. The result of these two considerations is that we must will maxims that can be at the same time universal, but which do not infringe on the freedom of ourselves nor of others. A universal maxim, however, could only
946:
The free will is the source of all rational action. But to treat it as a subjective end is to deny the possibility of freedom in general. Because the autonomous will is the one and only source of moral action, it would contradict the first formulation to claim that a person is merely a means to some
1067:
Because a truly autonomous will would not be subjugated to any interest, it would only be subject to those laws it makes for itself—but it must also regard those laws as if they would be bound to others, or they would not be universalizable, and hence they would not be laws of conduct at all. Thus,
1418:
Thus, insofar as individuals' freely chosen ends are consistent in a rational Idea of community of interdependent beings also exercising the possibility of their pure moral reason is the egoism self-justified as being what is 'holy' good will because the motive is consistent with what all rational
1312:
and necessarily universally binding rule on all rational agents. The Golden Rule, on the other hand, is neither purely formal nor necessarily universally binding. It is "empirical" in the sense that applying it depends on providing content, such as, "If you don't want others to hit you, then don't
961:
would be effectively asserting a moral right to own a person as a slave, they would be asserting a property right in another person. This would violate the categorical imperative, because it denies the basis for there to be free rational action at all; it denies the status of a person as an end in
1208:
is of charity. He proposes a fourth man who finds his own life fine but sees other people struggling with life and who ponders the outcome of doing nothing to help those in need (while not envying them or accepting anything from them). While Kant admits that humanity could subsist (and admits it
1145:
consent is a violation of perfect duty as interpreted through the second formulation. If a thief were to steal a book from an unknowing victim, it may have been that the victim would have agreed, had the thief simply asked. However, no person can consent to theft, because the presence of consent
917:
Second, we have imperfect duties, which are still based on pure reason, but which allow for desires in how they are carried out in practice. Because these depend somewhat on the subjective preferences of humankind, this duty is not as strong as a perfect duty, but it is still morally binding. As
1328:
Kant's objection to the Golden Rule is especially suspect because the categorical imperative (CI) sounds a lot like a paraphrase, or perhaps a close cousin, of the same fundamental idea. In effect, it says that you should act toward others in ways that you would want everyone else to act toward
1247:
Instead of resolving the problems of the poor and thinking of how the world can be different, some can only propose a reduction in the birth rate. ... To blame population growth instead of extreme and selective consumerism on the part of some, is one way of refusing to face the issues. It is an
962:
themselves. One cannot, on Kant's account, ever suppose a right to treat another person as a mere means to an end. In the case of a slave owner, the slaves are being used to cultivate the owner's fields (the slaves acting as the means) to ensure a sufficient harvest (the end goal of the owner).
942:
Every rational action must set before itself not only a principle, but also an end. Most ends are of a subjective kind, because they need only be pursued if they are in line with some particular hypothetical imperative that a person may choose to adopt. For an end to be objective, it would be
504:
apply to someone who wishes to attain certain ends. For example, "I must drink something to quench my thirst" or "I must study to pass this exam." The categorical imperative, on the other hand, commands immediately the maxims one conceives which match its categorical requirements, denoting an
1132:
The right to deceive could also not be claimed because it would deny the status of the person deceived as an end in itself. The theft would be incompatible with a possible kingdom of ends. Therefore, Kant denied the right to lie or deceive for any reason, regardless of context or anticipated
1125:, Kant gives the example of a person who seeks to borrow money without intending to pay it back. This is a contradiction because if it were a universal action, no person would lend money anymore as he knows that he will never be paid back. The maxim of this action, says Kant, results in a 838:
A moral maxim must imply absolute necessity, which is to say that it must be disconnected from the particular physical details surrounding the proposition, and could be applied to any rational being. This leads to the first formulation of the categorical imperative, sometimes called the
636:, he would necessarily fall under the natural law of desires and inclinations. However, since the world of understanding contains the ground of the world of sense, and thus of its laws, his actions ought to conform to the autonomy of the will, and this categorical "ought" represents a 1415:– since in restricting the will's motive at its root to a purely moral schema consistent its maxims can be held up to the pure moral law as a structure of cognition and therefore the alteration of action accompanying a cultured person to a 'reverence for the law' or 'moral feeling'. 793:. Since even a free person could not possibly have knowledge of their own freedom, we cannot use our failure to find a proof for freedom as evidence for a lack of it. The observable world could never contain an example of freedom because it would never show us a will as it appears to 1192:
e cannot possibly will that this should become a universal law of nature or be implanted in us as such a law by a natural instinct. For as a rational being he necessarily wills that all his faculties should be developed, inasmuch as they are given him for all sorts of possible
1014:
The result, of course, is a formulation of the categorical imperative that contains much of the same as the first two. We must will something that we could at the same time freely will of ourselves. After introducing this third formulation, Kant introduces a distinction between
1434:
Kant was of the opinion that man is his own law (autonomy)—that is, he binds himself under the law which he himself gives himself. Actually, in a profounder sense, this is how lawlessness or experimentation are established. This is not being rigorously earnest any more than
1410:
also holds not merely the positive form freedom (to set ends freely) but also the negative forms of freedom to that same will (to restrict setting of ends that treat others merely as means, etc.). The deontological system is for Kant argued to be based in a
1269:. Unlike in conventional game theory, a superrational player will act as if all other players are superrational too and that a superrational agent will always come up with the same strategy as any other superrational agent when facing the same problem. 1007:
have this form if it were a maxim that each subject by himself endorsed. Because it cannot be something which externally constrains each subject's activity, it must be a constraint that each subject has set for himself. This leads to the concept of
1346:, who asserted that since truth telling must be universal, according to Kant's theories, one must (if asked) tell a known murderer the location of his prey. This challenge occurred while Kant was still alive, and his response was the essay 1429:
believed Kantian autonomy was insufficient and that, if unchecked, people tend to be lenient in their own cases, either by not exercising the full rigor of the moral law or by not properly disciplining themselves of moral transgressions.
1248:
attempt to legitimize the present model of distribution, where a minority believes that it has the right to consume in a way which can never be universalized, since the planet could not even contain the waste products of such consumption.
782:. Applied to a case of the human will, a determinist would argue that the will does not have causal power and that something outside the will causes the will to act as it does. But this argument merely assumes what it sets out to prove: 1011:-legislation. Each subject must through his own use of reason will maxims which have the form of universality, but do not impinge on the freedom of others: thus each subject must will maxims that could be universally self-legislated. 528:
says that murder is wrong because it does not maximize good for those involved, but this is irrelevant to people who are concerned only with maximizing the positive outcome for themselves. Consequently, Kant argued, hypothetical
969:
to further the ends of ourselves and others. If any person desires perfection in themselves or others, it would be their moral duty to seek that end for all people equally, so long as that end does not contradict perfect duty.
1027:(literally: other-law-giving). This third formulation makes it clear that the categorical imperative requires autonomy. It is not enough that the right conduct be followed, but that one also demands that conduct of oneself. 797:, but only a will that is subject to natural laws imposed on it. But we do appear to ourselves as free. Therefore, he argued for the idea of transcendental freedom—that is, freedom as a presupposition of the question "what 603:
What dictates which action can be genuinely considered moral are maxims willed to action from the categorical imperative, separate from observable experience. This distinction, that it is imperative that each action is not
869:
that we have to ourselves versus those we have to others. For example, we have an obligation not to kill ourselves as well as an obligation not to kill others. Kant also, however, introduces a distinction between
1214:
in which one would have need of the love and sympathy of others and in which he would deprive himself, by such a law of nature springing from his own will, of all hope of the aid he wants for himself.
437: 1146:
would mean that the transfer was not a theft. Because the victim could not have consented to the action, it could not be instituted as a universal law of nature, and theft contradicts perfect duty.
1064:
There is, however, another formulation that has received additional attention as it appears to introduce a social dimension into Kant's thought. This is the formulation of the "Kingdom of Ends."
835:
Kant concludes that a moral proposition that is true must be one that is not tied to any particular conditions, including the identity and desires of the person making the moral deliberation.
1853: 1387: 886:
According to Kant's reasoning, we first have a perfect duty not to act by maxims that result in logical contradictions when we attempt to universalize them. The moral proposition
928:
Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never merely as a means to an end, but always at the same time as an end.
533:
cannot determine moral action or be regarded as bases for legitimate moral judgments against others, because the imperatives on which they are based rely too heavily on
570:
tell us which means best achieve our ends. They do not, however, tell us which ends we should choose. The typical dichotomy in choosing ends is between ends that are
1348: 226: 1068:
Kant presents the notion of the hypothetical Kingdom of Ends of which he suggests all people should consider themselves never solely as means but always as ends.
1002:
conditions on the categorical imperative: that it be universal in form and thus capable of becoming a law of nature. Likewise, the second formulation lays out
1850: 713:
by impulses, and is therefore of itself (apart from an acquired proficiency of reason) not pure but can still be determined to actions by pure will.
1356:). In this reply, Kant agreed with Constant's inference, that from Kant's own premises one must infer a moral duty not to lie to a murderer. 1780:
These additional formulations, of which there are at least eight, can be seen at: 4:434 (1); 4:436–7 (1); 4:437 (4); 4:438 (1); 4:438–9 (1).
1452:
However, many of Kierkegaard's criticisms on his understanding of Kantian autonomy, neglect the evolution of Kant's moral theory from the
1557:
occurs in the fourth volume. Citations throughout this article follow the format 4:x. For example, the above citation is taken from 4:421.
1360:
the rationality of another person, and therefore denies the possibility of there being free rational action at all. This lie results in a
1379:) is consistent with the categorical imperative, but assume for the purposes of argument that refusing to answer would not be an option. 1075:
not to act by maxims that create incoherent or impossible states of natural affairs when we attempt to universalize them, and we have
205: 86: 1099:) rather than our rational powers, this section explores some applications of the categorical imperative for illustrative purposes. 750:
Although Kant conceded that there could be no conceivable example of free will, because any example would only show us a will as it
677:. The faculty of desire whose inner determining ground, hence even what pleases it, lies within the subject's reason is called the 58: 537:
considerations. He presented a deontological moral system, based on the demands of the categorical imperative, as an alternative.
1303: 1204: 1156: 465: 212: 39: 1179: 184: 624:
Rational persons regard themselves as belonging to both the world of understanding and the world of sense. As a member of the
65: 2059: 1658: 330: 166: 980:
Thus the third practical principle follows as the ultimate condition of their harmony with practical reason: the idea of
2147: 72: 2022: 1488: 298: 1984: 1539: 105: 1329:
others, yourself included (presumably). Calling it a universal law does not materially improve on the basic concept.
586:; to him, the latter was morally dependent on the former. In Kant's view, a person cannot decide whether conduct is 54: 846:: "Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law." 481: 865:
Kant divides the duties imposed by this formulation into two sets of two subsets. The first division is between
524:
of his day, believing that it could never surpass the merely conditional command of hypothetical imperatives: a
1108: 43: 902:
universalized, then there could be no personal property, and so the proposition has logically negated itself.
890:: "It is permissible to steal" would result in a contradiction upon universalisation. The notion of stealing 821:
Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.
358: 191: 2200: 2137: 2160: 608:
determined by observable experience, has had wide social impact in the legal and political concepts of
801:
I to do?" This is what gives us sufficient basis for ascribing moral responsibility: the rational and
1826: 853:
formulation. Because laws of nature are by definition universal, Kant claims we may also express the
641: 368: 287: 219: 143: 505:
absolute, unconditional requirement that must be obeyed in all circumstances and is justified as an
79: 1594: 1568: 1160:, Kant applies his categorical imperative to the issue of suicide motivated by a sickness of life: 1043:
Act according to maxims of a universally legislating member of a merely possible kingdom of ends.
950:
On this basis, Kant derives the second formulation of the categorical imperative from the first.
567: 501: 318: 260: 175: 159: 32: 1243:, applies the first formulation of the universalizability principle to the issue of consumption: 1483: 1231: 861:
Act as if the maxims of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature.
600:, using pure practical reason independently of the influence of felt motives, or inclinations. 412: 353: 127: 758:. He proposed that determinism is logically inconsistent: the determinist claims that because 2153: 1531: 1088: 1071:
We ought to act only by maxims that would harmonize with a possible kingdom of ends. We have
637: 552: 1976: 1473: 198: 1426: 957:
not to use the humanity of themselves or others merely as a means to some other end. As a
8: 2195: 2190: 1169:
How the Categorical Imperative would apply to suicide from other motivations is unclear.
743:, is incomprehensible. Therefore, a free will must be acting under laws that it gives to 373: 335: 265: 2146:, a website on the presence and diffusion of the philosophy of Immanuel Kant in Italy ( 1930: 1922: 1887: 1423:) which is reason in its pure practical form. That is, morality seen deontologically. 1262: 1224: 842: 802: 657: 595: 591: 474: 473:
for action. It is best known in its original formulation: "Act only according to that
2174: 2119: 2111: 2055: 2018: 1980: 1934: 1664: 1654: 1535: 1524: 1343: 1121:
of any kind, would be forbidden under any interpretation and in any circumstance. In
1079:
not to act by maxims that lead to unstable or greatly undesirable states of affairs.
895: 661: 423: 1846:
Encyclical Letter Laudato si' of the Holy Father Francis on Care for Our Common Home
1947: 1914: 1879: 1498: 1287: 1258: 740: 564:, by which we determine ourselves to practical action within the phenomenal world. 561: 521: 1619: 1857: 1317: 1092: 1036: 906: 613: 441: 396: 324: 308: 277: 2123: 1918: 1844: 1593:
Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2022), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.),
1567:
Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2022), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.),
891: 807: 456: 401: 378: 253: 477:
whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law."
2184: 2143: 2070: 1321: 506: 460: 453: 282: 235: 135: 1668: 1232:
Application of the universalizability principle to the ethics of consumption
1141:
Kant argued that any action taken against another person to which he or she
1840: 1436: 1399: 1395: 1282:
The first formulation of the categorical imperative appears similar to the
1236: 673:(WillkĂĽr); if it is not joined with this consciousness its act is called a 609: 534: 530: 1964: 1648: 1478: 1291: 1283: 1266: 953:
By combining this formulation with the first, we learn that a person has
755: 654: 605: 557: 525: 497: 271: 814: 689:
can be included under the will. That choice which can be determined by
1891: 1493: 1407: 1240: 1023: 470: 449: 363: 249: 1926: 1972: 1530:. Translated by Ellington, James W. (3rd ed.). Hackett. p.  1118: 1087:
Although Kant was intensely critical of the use of examples as moral
736: 732: 2106: 1883: 1338:
One of the first major challenges to Kant's reasoning came from the
560:, which is the capacity to know without having been shown; and mere 21: 2127: 1601:(Fall 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 1575:(Fall 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 1548: 1017: 629: 485: 303: 1209:
could possibly perform better) if this were universal, he states:
982:
the will of every rational being as a universally legislating will
754:
to us—as a subject of natural laws—he nevertheless argued against
735:
power without being caused to do so. However, the idea of lawless
2017:. Boston, London, Sydney, Toronto: Allyn and Bacon. p. 139. 1458:
The Critique of Practical Reason, The Critique of Moral Judgment,
1096: 958: 909:
if not met, as they are a basic required duty for a human being.
1391: 1339: 489: 1228:
man. Therefore, man is obliged not to treat animals brutally.
492:, from which all duties and obligations derive. He defines an 488:
can be summed up in an imperative, or ultimate commandment of
1692:
Kant's Conceptions of the Categorical Imperative and the Will
1308:
Rather, the categorical imperative is an attempt to identify
1202:
Kant's last application of the categorical imperative in the
693:
is called free choice. That which can be determined only by
550:
The capacity that underlies deciding what is moral is called
1354:
On a Supposed Right to Lie because of Philanthropic Concerns
2054:, footnote 12. Cambridge University Press (28 April 1998). 866: 783: 520:
Kant expressed his strong dissatisfaction with the popular
2133:
An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy
1905:
Diekmann, Andreas (December 1985). "Volunteer's Dilemma".
1030: 811:: "the property the will has of being a law unto itself." 705:). Human choice, however, is a choice that can indeed be 500:
declaring a certain action (or inaction) to be necessary.
1114: 1349:
On a Supposed Right to Tell Lies from Benevolent Motives
2158: 2013:
Alston, William P.; Brandt, Richard B., eds. (1978).
1783: 815:
First formulation: Universality and the law of nature
1398:
claimed that the categorical imperative is actually
1177:
Kant also applies the categorical imperative in the
998:
Kant claims that the first formulation lays out the
947:
other end, rather than always an end in themselves.
2107:
Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals
46:. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. 1653:. Marcus Weigelt, F. Max MĂĽller. London: Penguin. 1523: 1456:, to the second and final critiques respectively, 1388:Schopenhauer's criticism of the Kantian philosophy 1368:) and therefore the lie is in conflict with duty. 786:that the human will is part of the causal chain. 628:, a person's actions would always conform to the 2182: 731:, we must understand it as capable of affecting 1620:"20th WCP: Why Couldn't Kant Be A Utilitarian?" 921: 849:Closely connected with this formulation is the 578:(e.g., enriching oneself). Kant considered the 1592: 1566: 973: 905:In general, perfect duties are those that are 1870:Campbell, Paul J. (January 1984). "Reviews". 2012: 2080: 1963: 1517: 1515: 1513: 943:necessary that we categorically pursue it. 574:(e.g., helping someone) and those that are 118:Central concept in Kantian moral philosophy 1390:expresses doubt concerning the absence of 1257:One form of the categorical imperative is 142: 965:The second formulation also leads to the 789:Secondly, Kant remarks that free will is 206:Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason 106:Learn how and when to remove this message 1904: 1869: 1510: 545: 484:occupy a special place in creation, and 178:​ Question: What Is Enlightenment? 2052:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 2003:p. 234. Ignatius Press. Kindle Edition. 1704: 1702: 1700: 1599:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1573:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1526:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 1460:and his final work on moral theory the 1382: 1304:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 1205:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 1157:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 1050:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 1031:Fourth formulation: The Kingdom of Ends 991:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 935:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 828:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 648: 466:Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals 2183: 1753: 1333: 1180:Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals 653:Kant viewed the human individual as a 594:means. Such judgments must be reached 185:Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals 2089:Kierkegaard and Kant: The Hidden Debt 2086: 1546:It is standard to also reference the 1375:the murderer's question (rather than 1301:Kant himself did not think so in the 1218: 227:On a Supposed Right to Tell Lies from 2044: 1813: 1801: 1789: 1759: 1738: 1726: 1697: 1646: 1642: 1640: 1521: 1364:(rather than the more practical one 739:, meaning a will acting without any 44:adding citations to reliable sources 15: 1454:Groundwork of Metaphysics of Morals 1223:Kant derived a prohibition against 13: 2124:Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms 1907:The Journal of Conflict Resolution 1489:Instrumental and value rationality 1277: 805:power of a person, which he calls 14: 2212: 2098: 1637: 1021:(literally: self-law-giving) and 912: 2168: 1261:. The concept was elucidated by 417: 20: 2064: 2031: 2006: 1993: 1957: 1941: 1898: 1863: 1834: 1819: 1807: 1795: 1774: 1765: 1744: 1732: 1720: 1394:in the categorical imperative. 1127:contradiction in conceivability 881: 31:needs additional citations for 1711: 1684: 1675: 1612: 1586: 1560: 1252: 1109:Doctrine of mental reservation 1091:, as they tend to rely on our 1082: 632:of the will. As a part of the 619: 299:Analytic–synthetic distinction 169:​ Any Future Metaphysics 1: 2129:Kant's System of Perspectives 2091:. SUNY Press. pp. 90–91. 1967:, ed. (1979). "golden rule". 1690:e.g. Pelegrinis, T. N. 1980. 1504: 1371:Constant and Kant agree that 1272: 669:by one's action it is called 1102: 922:Second formulation: Humanity 727:For a will to be considered 556:, which is contrasted with: 469:, it is a way of evaluating 463:. Introduced in Kant's 1785 192:Critique of Practical Reason 7: 2138:University Press of America 1919:10.1177/0022002785029004003 1467: 1362:contradiction in conception 1172: 974:Third formulation: Autonomy 10: 2217: 2154:The Categorical Imperative 2015:The Problems of Philosophy 1969:A Dictionary of Philosophy 1952:Confucius: The Golden Rule 1197: 1149: 1106: 1034: 701:) would be animal choice ( 540: 513:value beyond simply being 229:​ Benevolent Motives 1595:"Kant's Moral Philosophy" 1569:"Kant's Moral Philosophy" 1298:is deceived by the lie." 220:The Metaphysics of Morals 1522:Kant, Immanuel (1993) . 1136: 568:Hypothetical imperatives 502:Hypothetical imperatives 55:"Categorical imperative" 2144:Immanuel Kant in Italia 1650:Critique of pure reason 1647:Kant, Immanuel (2007). 1421:Critique of Pure Reason 446:kategorischer Imperativ 319:Hypothetical imperative 261:Transcendental idealism 160:Critique of Pure Reason 2087:Green, Ronald (1992). 2037:Kreeft, Peter (2009). 1484:Generalization (logic) 1450: 1352:(sometimes translated 1331: 1250: 1216: 1195: 1167: 1054: 995: 939: 863: 855:categorical imperative 832: 725: 626:world of understanding 445: 433:categorical imperative 314:Categorical imperative 1828:Metaphysics of Morals 1553:of Kant's works. The 1462:Metaphysics of Morals 1432: 1326: 1265:as a new approach to 1245: 1211: 1190: 1162: 1107:Further information: 1041: 978: 926: 859: 819: 791:inherently unknowable 778:is the true cause of 720:Metaphysics of Morals 666: 638:synthetic proposition 553:pure practical reason 546:Pure practical reason 424:Philosophy portal 1975:in association with 1872:Mathematics Magazine 1856:3 March 2016 at the 1729:, p. 36. 4:429. 1474:Deontological ethics 1383:Questioning autonomy 1320:thought so as well, 660:being with "impure" 649:Freedom and autonomy 590:, or moral, through 331:Political philosophy 199:Critique of Judgment 40:improve this article 2039:Socrates Meets Kant 2001:Socrates Meets Kant 1977:The MacMillan Press 1762:, p. 44. 4:439 1741:, p. 43. 4:431 1446:Papers and Journals 1444:Søren Kierkegaard, 1334:Lying to a murderer 1241:his 2015 encyclical 1113:Kant asserted that 697:(sensible impulse, 480:According to Kant, 374:Arthur Schopenhauer 266:Critical philosophy 2201:Ethical principles 2120:Palmquist, Stephen 1413:synthetic a priori 1373:refusing to answer 1263:Douglas Hofstadter 1225:cruelty to animals 1219:Cruelty to animals 1143:could not possibly 843:universalizability 415: • 252: • 2112:Project Gutenberg 2060:978-0-521-62695-8 1948:Freedman, Russell 1792:, pp. 30–31. 1660:978-0-14-044747-7 1427:Søren Kierkegaard 1344:Benjamin Constant 896:personal property 894:the existence of 662:freedom of choice 448:) is the central 429: 428: 116: 115: 108: 90: 2208: 2173: 2172: 2171: 2164: 2114: 2093: 2092: 2084: 2078: 2075:The Fair Society 2068: 2062: 2048: 2042: 2041:p. 236. Ignatius 2035: 2029: 2028: 2010: 2004: 1997: 1991: 1990: 1961: 1955: 1945: 1939: 1938: 1902: 1896: 1895: 1867: 1861: 1843:. May 24, 2015. 1838: 1832: 1823: 1817: 1811: 1805: 1799: 1793: 1787: 1781: 1778: 1772: 1771:4:431–2; 4:435–6 1769: 1763: 1757: 1751: 1748: 1742: 1736: 1730: 1724: 1718: 1715: 1709: 1706: 1695: 1688: 1682: 1679: 1673: 1672: 1644: 1635: 1634: 1632: 1630: 1616: 1610: 1609: 1608: 1606: 1590: 1584: 1583: 1582: 1580: 1564: 1558: 1545: 1529: 1519: 1499:Normative ethics 1448: 1259:superrationality 1128: 1093:moral intuitions 1052: 993: 937: 876:imperfect duties 830: 803:self-actualizing 741:causal structure 723: 703:arbitrium brutum 562:practical reason 522:moral philosophy 457:moral philosophy 440: 422: 421: 420: 228: 177: 168: 146: 123: 122: 111: 104: 100: 97: 91: 89: 48: 24: 16: 2216: 2215: 2211: 2210: 2209: 2207: 2206: 2205: 2181: 2180: 2179: 2169: 2167: 2159: 2104: 2101: 2096: 2085: 2081: 2069: 2065: 2050:Kant, Immanuel 2049: 2045: 2036: 2032: 2025: 2011: 2007: 1998: 1994: 1987: 1979:. p. 134. 1962: 1958: 1946: 1942: 1903: 1899: 1884:10.2307/2690298 1868: 1864: 1858:Wayback Machine 1839: 1835: 1824: 1820: 1812: 1808: 1800: 1796: 1788: 1784: 1779: 1775: 1770: 1766: 1758: 1754: 1749: 1745: 1737: 1733: 1725: 1721: 1716: 1712: 1707: 1698: 1689: 1685: 1680: 1676: 1661: 1645: 1638: 1628: 1626: 1618: 1617: 1613: 1604: 1602: 1591: 1587: 1578: 1576: 1565: 1561: 1542: 1520: 1511: 1507: 1470: 1449: 1443: 1385: 1336: 1310:a purely formal 1280: 1278:The Golden Rule 1275: 1255: 1234: 1221: 1200: 1175: 1152: 1139: 1126: 1111: 1105: 1085: 1055: 1053: 1048:Immanuel Kant, 1047: 1039: 1037:Kingdom of Ends 1033: 996: 994: 989:Immanuel Kant, 988: 976: 940: 938: 933:Immanuel Kant, 932: 924: 915: 884: 833: 831: 826:Immanuel Kant, 825: 817: 724: 718:Immanuel Kant, 717: 651: 622: 548: 543: 482:rational beings 452:concept in the 436: 418: 416: 407: 406: 397:German idealism 392: 384: 383: 349: 341: 340: 325:Kingdom of Ends 278:Thing-in-itself 256: 242: 241: 213:Perpetual Peace 154: 119: 112: 101: 95: 92: 49: 47: 37: 25: 12: 11: 5: 2214: 2204: 2203: 2198: 2193: 2178: 2177: 2157: 2156: 2151: 2141: 2116: 2115: 2100: 2099:External links 2097: 2095: 2094: 2079: 2071:Corning, Peter 2063: 2043: 2030: 2024:978-0205061105 2023: 2005: 1992: 1985: 1956: 1940: 1913:(4): 605–610. 1897: 1862: 1833: 1818: 1806: 1794: 1782: 1773: 1764: 1752: 1743: 1731: 1719: 1710: 1696: 1683: 1674: 1659: 1636: 1611: 1585: 1559: 1540: 1508: 1506: 1503: 1502: 1501: 1496: 1491: 1486: 1481: 1476: 1469: 1466: 1441: 1384: 1381: 1335: 1332: 1324:suggests that: 1316:Claiming that 1279: 1276: 1274: 1271: 1254: 1251: 1233: 1230: 1220: 1217: 1199: 1196: 1174: 1171: 1151: 1148: 1138: 1135: 1133:consequences. 1104: 1101: 1084: 1081: 1077:imperfect duty 1045: 1040: 1035:Main article: 1032: 1029: 986: 977: 975: 972: 967:imperfect duty 930: 925: 923: 920: 914: 913:Imperfect duty 911: 883: 880: 823: 818: 816: 813: 808:moral autonomy 715: 685:but also mere 658:self-conscious 650: 647: 634:world of sense 621: 618: 547: 544: 542: 539: 427: 426: 409: 408: 405: 404: 402:Neo-Kantianism 399: 393: 391:Related topics 390: 389: 386: 385: 382: 381: 379:Baruch Spinoza 376: 371: 366: 361: 359:G. W. F. Hegel 356: 350: 347: 346: 343: 342: 339: 338: 333: 328: 321: 316: 311: 306: 301: 296: 285: 280: 275: 268: 263: 257: 254:Kantian ethics 248: 247: 244: 243: 240: 239: 232: 223: 216: 209: 202: 195: 188: 181: 172: 167:Prolegomena to 163: 155: 152: 151: 148: 147: 139: 138: 132: 131: 117: 114: 113: 28: 26: 19: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 2213: 2202: 2199: 2197: 2194: 2192: 2189: 2188: 2186: 2176: 2166: 2165: 2162: 2155: 2152: 2149: 2148:archived page 2145: 2142: 2139: 2135: 2134: 2130: 2125: 2121: 2118: 2117: 2113: 2109: 2108: 2103: 2102: 2090: 2083: 2076: 2072: 2067: 2061: 2057: 2053: 2047: 2040: 2034: 2026: 2020: 2016: 2009: 2002: 1996: 1988: 1986:0-330-48730-2 1982: 1978: 1974: 1970: 1966: 1960: 1953: 1949: 1944: 1936: 1932: 1928: 1924: 1920: 1916: 1912: 1908: 1901: 1893: 1889: 1885: 1881: 1877: 1873: 1866: 1859: 1855: 1852: 1848: 1847: 1842: 1837: 1830: 1829: 1822: 1815: 1810: 1803: 1798: 1791: 1786: 1777: 1768: 1761: 1756: 1747: 1740: 1735: 1728: 1723: 1714: 1705: 1703: 1701: 1693: 1687: 1678: 1670: 1666: 1662: 1656: 1652: 1651: 1643: 1641: 1625: 1621: 1615: 1600: 1596: 1589: 1574: 1570: 1563: 1556: 1552: 1550: 1543: 1541:0-87220-166-X 1537: 1533: 1528: 1527: 1518: 1516: 1514: 1509: 1500: 1497: 1495: 1492: 1490: 1487: 1485: 1482: 1480: 1477: 1475: 1472: 1471: 1465: 1463: 1459: 1455: 1447: 1440: 1438: 1431: 1428: 1424: 1422: 1416: 1414: 1409: 1404: 1401: 1397: 1393: 1389: 1380: 1378: 1374: 1369: 1367: 1363: 1357: 1355: 1351: 1350: 1345: 1341: 1330: 1325: 1323: 1322:Peter Corning 1319: 1314: 1311: 1307: 1305: 1299: 1297: 1293: 1289: 1288:negative form 1285: 1270: 1268: 1264: 1260: 1249: 1244: 1242: 1238: 1229: 1226: 1215: 1210: 1207: 1206: 1194: 1189: 1187: 1182: 1181: 1170: 1166: 1161: 1159: 1158: 1147: 1144: 1134: 1130: 1124: 1120: 1116: 1110: 1100: 1098: 1094: 1090: 1080: 1078: 1074: 1069: 1065: 1062: 1060: 1051: 1044: 1038: 1028: 1026: 1025: 1020: 1019: 1012: 1010: 1005: 1001: 992: 985: 983: 971: 968: 963: 960: 956: 951: 948: 944: 936: 929: 919: 910: 908: 903: 901: 897: 893: 889: 879: 877: 873: 868: 862: 858: 856: 852: 851:law of nature 847: 845: 844: 841:principle of 836: 829: 822: 812: 810: 809: 804: 800: 796: 792: 787: 785: 781: 777: 773: 769: 765: 761: 757: 753: 748: 746: 742: 738: 734: 730: 721: 714: 712: 708: 704: 700: 696: 692: 688: 684: 680: 676: 672: 665: 663: 659: 656: 646: 644: 643: 639: 635: 631: 627: 617: 615: 611: 607: 601: 599: 598: 593: 589: 585: 582:prior to the 581: 577: 573: 569: 565: 563: 559: 555: 554: 538: 536: 532: 531:moral systems 527: 523: 518: 516: 512: 509:, possessing 508: 507:end in itself 503: 499: 495: 491: 487: 483: 478: 476: 472: 468: 467: 462: 461:Immanuel Kant 458: 455: 454:deontological 451: 450:philosophical 447: 443: 439: 434: 425: 414: 411: 410: 403: 400: 398: 395: 394: 388: 387: 380: 377: 375: 372: 370: 367: 365: 362: 360: 357: 355: 352: 351: 345: 344: 337: 334: 332: 329: 326: 322: 320: 317: 315: 312: 310: 307: 305: 302: 300: 297: 295: 294: 290: 286: 284: 281: 279: 276: 274: 273: 269: 267: 264: 262: 259: 258: 255: 251: 246: 245: 238: 237: 236:Opus Postumum 233: 230: 224: 222: 221: 217: 215: 214: 210: 208: 207: 203: 201: 200: 196: 194: 193: 189: 187: 186: 182: 179: 176:Answering the 173: 171: 170: 164: 162: 161: 157: 156: 150: 149: 145: 141: 140: 137: 136:Immanuel Kant 134: 133: 129: 125: 124: 121: 110: 107: 99: 88: 85: 81: 78: 74: 71: 67: 64: 60: 57: â€“  56: 52: 51:Find sources: 45: 41: 35: 34: 29:This article 27: 23: 18: 17: 2132: 2128: 2105: 2088: 2082: 2074: 2066: 2051: 2046: 2038: 2033: 2014: 2008: 2000: 1995: 1968: 1959: 1951: 1943: 1910: 1906: 1900: 1878:(1): 51–55. 1875: 1871: 1865: 1845: 1841:Pope Francis 1836: 1827: 1821: 1816:, p. 32 1809: 1804:, p. 31 1797: 1785: 1776: 1767: 1755: 1746: 1734: 1722: 1713: 1691: 1686: 1677: 1649: 1627:. Retrieved 1623: 1614: 1603:, retrieved 1598: 1588: 1577:, retrieved 1572: 1562: 1554: 1547: 1525: 1461: 1457: 1453: 1451: 1445: 1437:Sancho Panza 1433: 1425: 1420: 1417: 1412: 1405: 1400:hypothetical 1396:Schopenhauer 1386: 1376: 1372: 1370: 1365: 1361: 1358: 1353: 1347: 1342:philosopher 1337: 1327: 1315: 1309: 1302: 1300: 1295: 1281: 1256: 1246: 1237:Pope Francis 1235: 1222: 1212: 1203: 1201: 1191: 1185: 1178: 1176: 1168: 1163: 1155: 1153: 1142: 1140: 1131: 1122: 1112: 1086: 1076: 1073:perfect duty 1072: 1070: 1066: 1063: 1058: 1056: 1049: 1042: 1022: 1016: 1013: 1008: 1003: 999: 997: 990: 981: 979: 966: 964: 955:perfect duty 954: 952: 949: 945: 941: 934: 927: 916: 904: 899: 887: 885: 882:Perfect duty 875: 871: 864: 860: 854: 850: 848: 840: 837: 834: 827: 820: 806: 798: 794: 790: 788: 779: 775: 771: 767: 763: 759: 751: 749: 744: 728: 726: 719: 710: 706: 702: 698: 694: 690: 686: 682: 678: 674: 670: 667: 652: 640: 633: 625: 623: 610:human rights 602: 596: 587: 583: 579: 575: 571: 566: 551: 549: 519: 514: 510: 493: 479: 464: 432: 430: 369:F. H. Jacobi 354:J. G. Fichte 313: 293:a posteriori 292: 288: 270: 234: 218: 211: 204: 197: 190: 183: 165: 158: 120: 102: 93: 83: 76: 69: 62: 50: 38:Please help 33:verification 30: 1965:Antony Flew 1479:Golden Rule 1318:Ken Binmore 1292:Golden Rule 1284:Golden Rule 1267:game theory 1253:Game theory 1083:Application 959:slave owner 907:blameworthy 898:, but were 892:presupposes 756:determinism 695:inclination 691:pure reason 620:Possibility 606:empirically 558:pure reason 526:utilitarian 498:proposition 471:motivations 272:Sapere aude 153:Major works 96:August 2022 2196:Kantianism 2191:Deontology 2185:Categories 2175:Philosophy 1971:. London: 1624:www.bu.edu 1555:Groundwork 1505:References 1494:Kantianism 1408:deontology 1273:Criticisms 1186:Groundwork 1123:Groundwork 1089:yardsticks 1059:Groundwork 1024:heteronomy 1004:subjective 711:determined 655:rationally 535:subjective 494:imperative 364:David Hume 250:Kantianism 66:newspapers 2122:. 1993. " 1973:Pan Books 1935:143954605 1814:Kant 1993 1802:Kant 1993 1790:Kant 1993 1760:Kant 1993 1739:Kant 1993 1727:Kant 1993 1406:However, 1286:. In its 1193:purposes. 1119:deception 1103:Deception 1000:objective 737:free will 592:empirical 515:desirable 511:intrinsic 438:‹See Tfd› 336:Teleology 1854:Archived 1694:. p. 92. 1669:51622849 1549:Akademie 1468:See also 1442:—  1173:Laziness 1097:feelings 1046:—  1018:autonomy 987:—  931:—  824:—  716:—  709:but not 707:affected 699:stimulus 642:a priori 630:autonomy 614:equality 597:a priori 486:morality 413:Category 309:Category 304:Noumenon 289:A priori 128:a series 126:Part of 1892:2690298 1629:6 March 1605:6 March 1579:6 March 1551:Ausgabe 1366:in will 1198:Charity 1154:In the 1150:Suicide 1057:In the 872:perfect 774:, that 770:caused 762:caused 752:appears 722:6:213–4 541:Outline 496:as any 80:scholar 2161:Portal 2126:." In 2058:  2021:  1983:  1933:  1927:174243 1925:  1890:  1831:, § 17 1825:Kant, 1667:  1657:  1538:  1392:egoism 1340:French 867:duties 795:itself 766:, and 745:itself 733:causal 683:choice 671:choice 490:reason 442:German 348:People 283:Schema 82:  75:  68:  61:  53:  1931:S2CID 1923:JSTOR 1888:JSTOR 1750:4:431 1717:4:423 1708:4:421 1681:4:454 1377:lying 1239:, in 1137:Theft 1117:, or 1115:lying 799:ought 588:right 580:right 572:right 475:maxim 87:JSTOR 73:books 2056:ISBN 2019:ISBN 1981:ISBN 1851:§ 50 1665:OCLC 1655:ISBN 1631:2024 1607:2024 1581:2024 1536:ISBN 1009:self 874:and 784:viz. 729:free 687:wish 679:will 675:wish 612:and 584:good 576:good 431:The 291:and 59:news 2110:at 1915:doi 1880:doi 857:as: 517:. 459:of 42:by 2187:: 2136:. 2131:: 2073:. 1950:. 1929:. 1921:. 1911:29 1909:. 1886:. 1876:57 1874:. 1849:. 1699:^ 1663:. 1639:^ 1622:. 1597:, 1571:, 1534:. 1532:30 1512:^ 1464:. 1296:he 1188:: 878:. 747:. 664:: 645:. 616:. 444:: 130:on 2163:: 2150:) 2140:. 2077:. 2027:. 1989:. 1954:. 1937:. 1917:: 1894:. 1882:: 1860:. 1671:. 1633:. 1544:. 1306:. 1095:( 984:. 900:A 888:A 780:C 776:A 772:C 768:B 764:B 760:A 435:( 327:" 323:" 231:" 225:" 180:" 174:" 109:) 103:( 98:) 94:( 84:· 77:· 70:· 63:· 36:.

Index


verification
improve this article
adding citations to reliable sources
"Categorical imperative"
news
newspapers
books
scholar
JSTOR
Learn how and when to remove this message
a series
Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant
Critique of Pure Reason
Prolegomena to​ Any Future Metaphysics
Answering the​ Question: What Is Enlightenment?
Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals
Critique of Practical Reason
Critique of Judgment
Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason
Perpetual Peace
The Metaphysics of Morals
On a Supposed Right to Tell Lies from​ Benevolent Motives
Opus Postumum
Kantianism
Kantian ethics
Transcendental idealism
Critical philosophy
Sapere aude

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑