Knowledge

Causal theory of reference

Source 📝

137:
referent (Jane). That is, if I am in direct contact with Jane, the reference for my utterance of the name 'Jane' may be fixed not simply by a causal chain through people who had encountered her earlier (when she was first named); it may also be indexically fixed to Jane at the moment of my utterance. Thus our modern day use of a name such as 'Christopher Columbus' can be thought of as referring to Columbus through a causal chain that terminates not simply in one instance of his naming, but rather in a series of grounding uses of the name that occurred throughout his life. Under certain circumstances of confusion, this can lead to the alteration of a name's referent (for one example of how this might happen, see
168:", although many Frege scholars consider this attribution misguided). On such an account, the name 'Aristotle' might be seen as meaning 'the student of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great'. Later description theorists expanded upon this by suggesting that a name expressed not one particular description, but many (perhaps constituting all of one's essential knowledge of the individual named), or a weighted average of these descriptions. 336: 218:. Because speakers interact with a natural kind such as water regularly, and because there is generally no naming ceremony through which their names are formalized, the multiple groundings described above are even more essential to a causal account of such terms. A speaker whose environment changes may thus observe that the referents of his terms shift, as described in the 284:
argued that the causal theory, or at least certain common and over-simple variants of it, have the consequence that, however remote or obscure the causal connection between someone's use of a proper name and the object it originally referred to, they still refer to that object when they use the name.
319:
unknowingly referred to the African Island as "Madagascar" when the natives actually used the term to refer to a part of the mainland. Evans claims that Polo clearly intended to use the term as the natives do, but somehow changed the meaning of the term "Madagascar" to refer to the island as it is
123:
use the name 'Jane', they are referring to Jane? The answer provided by causal theories is that there is a causal chain that passes from the original observers of Jane's naming to everyone else who uses her name. For example, maybe Jill was not at the naming, but Jill learns about Jane, and learns
186:
other than 'the first European in North America' or 'the first person to believe that the earth was round'. Both of these beliefs are incorrect. Nevertheless, when such a person says 'Christopher Columbus', we acknowledge that they are referring to Christopher Columbus, not to whatever individual
115:
Such a causal process might proceed as follows: the parents of a newborn baby name it, pointing to the child and saying "we'll call her 'Jane'." Henceforth everyone calls her 'Jane'. With that act, the parents give the girl her name. The assembled family and friends now know that 'Jane' is a name
307:
argued for a causal theory similar to Kripke's, except that the baptised object is eliminated. A "baptism" may be a baptism of nothing, he argues: a name can be intelligibly introduced even if it names nothing. The causal chain we associate with the use of proper names may begin merely with a
136:
have insisted that the theory's account of the dubbing process needs to be broadened to include what are called 'multiple groundings'. After her initial baptism, uses of 'Jane' in the presence of Jane may, under the right circumstances, be considered to further ground the name ('Jane') in its
70:
Weaker versions of the position (perhaps not properly called "causal theories"), claim merely that, in many cases, events in the causal history of a speaker's use of the term, including when the term was first acquired, must be considered to correctly assign references to the speaker's words.
213:
The same motivations apply to causal theories in regard to other sorts of terms. Putnam, for instance, attempted to establish that 'water' refers rigidly to the stuff that we do in fact call 'water', to the exclusion of any possible identical water-like substance for which we have no causal
112:. Kripke argued that in order to use a name successfully to refer to something, you do not have to be acquainted with a uniquely identifying description of that thing. Rather, your use of the name need only be caused (in an appropriate way) by the naming of that thing. 292:
The links between different users of the name are particularly obscure. Each user must somehow pass the name on to the next, and must somehow "mean" the right individual as they do so (suppose "Socrates" is the name of a pet
128:
there. She then uses the name 'Jane' with the intention of referring to the child Jane's mother referred to. Jill can now use the name, and her use of it can in turn transmit the ability to refer to Jane to other speakers.
100:, Kripke provided a rough outline of his causal theory of reference for names. Although he refused to explicitly endorse such a theory, he indicated that such an approach was far more promising than the then-popular 198:, while a definite description does not. (One could say 'If Aristotle had died young, he would never have taught Alexander the Great.' But if 'the teacher of Alexander the Great' were a component of the 324:
claims that repeated groundings in an object can account for reference change. However, such a response leaves open the problem of cognitive significance that originally intrigued Russell and Frege.
206:
A causal theory avoids these difficulties. A name refers rigidly to the bearer to which it is causally connected, regardless of any particular facts about the bearer, and in all
182:
We can successfully refer to individuals for whom the only identifying descriptions we have fail to refer as we believe them to. (Many speakers have no identifying beliefs about
1319: 285:(Imagine a name briefly overheard in a train or café.) The theory effectively ignores context and makes reference into a magic trick. Evans describes it as a " 17: 149:
Causal theories of reference were born partially in response to the widespread acceptance of Russellian descriptive theories. Russell found that certain
692: 268:
in 1984, introduces the idea that a minimal descriptive apparatus needs to be added to the causal relations between speaker and object. (See also
663: 269: 1409: 1550: 1509: 1271: 179:
uniquely identifying description. (For example, a speaker can talk about Phillie Sophik even if one only knows him as 'some poet'.)
119:
However, not everyone who knows Jane and uses the name 'Jane' to refer to her was present at this naming. So how is it that when
437:
Thomas Kuhn's 'Linguistic Turn' and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism: Incommensurability, Rationality and the Search for Truth
1514: 685: 718: 373:
Donnellan, Keith. (1972). "Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions." In Donald Davidson; Gilbert Harman (eds.).
1504: 678: 43:
terms. In the case of names, for example, a causal theory of reference typically involves the following claims:
1484: 1349: 35:
based on evidence. Such theories have been used to describe many referring terms, particularly logical terms,
1540: 1230: 1009: 971: 921: 219: 138: 1479: 1379: 648:
Sainsbury, R.M. (2001). "Sense without Reference". In Newen, A.; Nortmann, U.; Stuhlmann Laisz, R. (eds.).
304: 1220: 1170: 101: 74:
Causal theories of names became popular during the 1970s, under the influence of work by Saul Kripke and
1359: 1099: 710: 553: 312: 281: 133: 62:
later uses of the name succeed in referring to the referent by being linked to that original act via a
1444: 1044: 951: 791: 354: 265: 615: 1369: 1014: 941: 796: 1260: 1104: 1039: 701: 610: 253:
in 1980. This view introduces the idea of reference-passing links in a causal-historical chain.
165: 601:
Machery, E.; Mallon, R.; Nichols, S.; Stich, S. P. (2004). "Semantics, Cross-cultural Style".
1235: 1215: 1150: 1034: 816: 109: 1399: 1309: 1108: 1069: 801: 215: 183: 157: 96: 8: 1449: 1439: 1289: 1245: 1079: 856: 771: 116:
which refers to Jane. This is referred to as Jane's dubbing, naming, or initial baptism.
483: 1545: 1299: 1195: 1190: 1114: 1089: 891: 876: 841: 657: 636: 557: 495: 226: 311:
The causal theory has a difficult time explaining the phenomenon of reference change.
1265: 1185: 1024: 906: 628: 487: 341: 640: 624: 1329: 1240: 1064: 1059: 861: 620: 479: 195: 105: 56: 31:
or historical chain theory of reference is a theory of how terms acquire specific
1474: 1389: 1145: 1124: 1074: 1054: 994: 961: 916: 911: 871: 756: 416: 246: 207: 171:
Kripke found this account to be deeply flawed, for a number of reasons. Notably:
75: 1535: 1225: 1180: 1004: 936: 806: 349: 321: 811: 1529: 1469: 1084: 989: 984: 946: 866: 846: 821: 786: 590: 584: 491: 161: 153: 79: 402: 1210: 1205: 1160: 1119: 1029: 931: 886: 881: 851: 836: 831: 632: 83: 40: 36: 1454: 1419: 1339: 1165: 956: 896: 781: 766: 670: 574: 298: 250: 52: 1459: 1250: 1094: 1049: 926: 901: 826: 761: 499: 316: 286: 470:
Evans, Gareth; Altham, J. E. J. (1973). "The Causal Theory of Names".
51:
is fixed by an original act of naming (also called a "dubbing" or, by
1491: 1200: 1140: 1019: 999: 751: 746: 726: 63: 48: 32: 245:
is the original version of the causal theory. It was put forward by
1464: 1155: 776: 736: 294: 223: 1175: 731: 1320:
An Essay Towards a Real Character, and a Philosophical Language
1255: 472:
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes
741: 150: 514:
Departing From Frege: Essays in the Philosophy of Language
386:
Kripke, S. "A Puzzle about Belief", in A. Margalit (ed.),
175:
We can successfully refer to individuals for whom we have
600: 55:, an "initial baptism"), whereupon the name becomes a 587:(1977) "On the Sense and Reference of a Proper Name." 331: 164:, mostly on the strength of a footnoted comment in " 156:
could be avoided if names were considered disguised
89: 194:have happened to a person. A name functions as a 124:that her name is 'Jane', from Jane's mother, who 108:, according to which names are in fact disguised 1527: 190:We use names to speak hypothetically about what 686: 581:. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. 82:also defended an analogous causal account of 421:Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth 412: 410: 202:of 'Aristotle' then this would be nonsense.) 469: 456:(3), 221–36; reprinted in D. Lewis (1999), 403:Names (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) 1410:Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language 700: 693: 679: 662:: CS1 maint: location missing publisher ( 276: 214:connection. These considerations motivate 647: 614: 556:(1985). "The Causal Theory of Names". In 537: 525: 407: 237:Variations of the causal theory include: 460:, Cambridge University Press, pp. 56–77. 448:D. K. Lewis (1984), "Putnam's Paradox." 431: 429: 297:). Kripke himself notes the difficulty, 160:(a similar view is often attributed to 14: 1528: 458:Papers on metaphysics and epistemology 262:causal-descriptive theory of reference 258:descriptive-causal theory of reference 674: 426: 398: 396: 243:causal-historical theory of reference 187:satisfies one of those descriptions.) 18:Causal-historical theory of reference 377:. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. pp. 356–379. 439:, Ashgate Publishing, 2012, p. 122. 24: 450:Australasian Journal of Philosophy 393: 25: 1562: 484:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/47.1.187 1551:Meaning (philosophy of language) 564:. Oxford University Press, 2012. 334: 90:Kripke's causal account of names 625:10.1016/j.cognition.2003.10.003 531: 94:In lectures later published as 1350:Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 519: 506: 463: 442: 380: 367: 13: 1: 1231:Principle of compositionality 547: 516:, Routledge, 2002, Essay XII. 375:Semantics of Natural Language 232: 144: 139:Twin Earth thought experiment 1380:Philosophical Investigations 390:, Reidel, pp. 239–83 (1979). 7: 1221:Modality (natural language) 327: 102:descriptive theory of names 10: 1567: 1360:Language, Truth, and Logic 1100:Theological noncognitivism 985:Contrast theory of meaning 980:Causal theory of reference 711:Index of language articles 569:The Varieties of Reference 562:The Philosophy of Language 423:, Routledge, 1999, p. 279. 315:cites the example of when 270:Criticism of structuralism 29:causal theory of reference 1500: 1445:Philosophy of information 1432: 1281: 1133: 1045:Mediated reference theory 970: 717: 708: 355:Mediated reference theory 264:), a view put forward by 210:where the bearer exists. 1370:Two Dogmas of Empiricism 360: 1171:Use–mention distinction 1015:Direct reference theory 308:"journalistic" source. 289:" theory of reference. 277:Criticism of the theory 1105:Theory of descriptions 1040:Linguistic determinism 702:Philosophy of language 166:On Sense and Reference 1216:Mental representation 1151:Linguistic relativity 1035:Inquisitive semantics 595:Reference and Essence 158:definite descriptions 132:Philosophers such as 110:definite descriptions 1541:Theories of language 1400:Naming and Necessity 1310:De Arte Combinatoria 1109:Definite description 1070:Semantic externalism 579:Naming and Necessity 216:semantic externalism 184:Christopher Columbus 97:Naming and Necessity 1450:Philosophical logic 1440:Analytic philosophy 1246:Sense and reference 1125:Verification theory 1080:Situation semantics 597:, Prometheus Books. 227:thought experiments 1300:Port-Royal Grammar 1196:Family resemblance 1115:Theory of language 1090:Supposition theory 301:makes much of it. 1523: 1522: 1025:Dynamic semantics 650:Building on Frege 512:Sainsbury, R.M., 342:Philosophy portal 16:(Redirected from 1558: 1485:Formal semantics 1433:Related articles 1425: 1415: 1405: 1395: 1385: 1375: 1365: 1355: 1345: 1335: 1325: 1315: 1305: 1295: 1065:Relevance theory 1060:Phallogocentrism 695: 688: 681: 672: 671: 667: 661: 653: 644: 618: 558:Martinich, A. P. 541: 535: 529: 523: 517: 510: 504: 503: 467: 461: 446: 440: 435:Stefano Gattei, 433: 424: 414: 405: 400: 391: 384: 378: 371: 344: 339: 338: 337: 196:rigid designator 57:rigid designator 21: 1566: 1565: 1561: 1560: 1559: 1557: 1556: 1555: 1526: 1525: 1524: 1519: 1496: 1475:School of Names 1428: 1423: 1413: 1403: 1393: 1390:Of Grammatology 1383: 1373: 1363: 1353: 1343: 1333: 1323: 1313: 1303: 1293: 1277: 1129: 1075:Semantic holism 1055:Non-cognitivism 995:Conventionalism 966: 713: 704: 699: 655: 654: 616:10.1.1.174.5119 585:McDowell, John. 550: 545: 544: 536: 532: 524: 520: 511: 507: 468: 464: 447: 443: 434: 427: 417:Stathis Psillos 415: 408: 401: 394: 388:Meaning and Use 385: 381: 372: 368: 363: 340: 335: 333: 330: 279: 247:Keith Donnellan 235: 208:possible worlds 147: 92: 76:Keith Donnellan 59:of that object. 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 1564: 1554: 1553: 1548: 1543: 1538: 1521: 1520: 1518: 1517: 1512: 1507: 1501: 1498: 1497: 1495: 1494: 1489: 1488: 1487: 1477: 1472: 1467: 1462: 1457: 1452: 1447: 1442: 1436: 1434: 1430: 1429: 1427: 1426: 1416: 1406: 1396: 1386: 1376: 1366: 1356: 1346: 1336: 1326: 1316: 1306: 1296: 1285: 1283: 1279: 1278: 1276: 1275: 1268: 1263: 1258: 1253: 1248: 1243: 1238: 1233: 1228: 1226:Presupposition 1223: 1218: 1213: 1208: 1203: 1198: 1193: 1188: 1183: 1178: 1173: 1168: 1163: 1158: 1153: 1148: 1143: 1137: 1135: 1131: 1130: 1128: 1127: 1122: 1117: 1112: 1102: 1097: 1092: 1087: 1082: 1077: 1072: 1067: 1062: 1057: 1052: 1047: 1042: 1037: 1032: 1027: 1022: 1017: 1012: 1007: 1005:Deconstruction 1002: 997: 992: 987: 982: 976: 974: 968: 967: 965: 964: 959: 954: 949: 944: 939: 934: 929: 924: 919: 914: 909: 904: 899: 894: 889: 884: 879: 874: 869: 864: 859: 854: 849: 844: 839: 834: 829: 824: 819: 814: 809: 804: 799: 794: 789: 784: 779: 774: 769: 764: 759: 754: 749: 744: 739: 734: 729: 723: 721: 715: 714: 709: 706: 705: 698: 697: 690: 683: 675: 669: 668: 645: 598: 591:Salmon, Nathan 588: 582: 572: 571:, Oxford 1982. 565: 549: 546: 543: 542: 538:Sainsbury 2001 530: 526:Sainsbury 2001 518: 505: 462: 441: 425: 406: 392: 379: 365: 364: 362: 359: 358: 357: 352: 350:Brain in a vat 346: 345: 329: 326: 322:Michael Devitt 305:Mark Sainsbury 278: 275: 274: 273: 254: 234: 231: 204: 203: 188: 180: 154:contradictions 146: 143: 104:introduced by 91: 88: 68: 67: 60: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1563: 1552: 1549: 1547: 1544: 1542: 1539: 1537: 1534: 1533: 1531: 1516: 1513: 1511: 1508: 1506: 1503: 1502: 1499: 1493: 1490: 1486: 1483: 1482: 1481: 1478: 1476: 1473: 1471: 1470:Scholasticism 1468: 1466: 1463: 1461: 1458: 1456: 1453: 1451: 1448: 1446: 1443: 1441: 1438: 1437: 1435: 1431: 1422: 1421: 1417: 1412: 1411: 1407: 1402: 1401: 1397: 1392: 1391: 1387: 1382: 1381: 1377: 1372: 1371: 1367: 1362: 1361: 1357: 1352: 1351: 1347: 1341: 1337: 1332: 1331: 1327: 1322: 1321: 1317: 1312: 1311: 1307: 1302: 1301: 1297: 1292: 1291: 1287: 1286: 1284: 1280: 1274: 1273: 1269: 1267: 1264: 1262: 1259: 1257: 1254: 1252: 1249: 1247: 1244: 1242: 1239: 1237: 1234: 1232: 1229: 1227: 1224: 1222: 1219: 1217: 1214: 1212: 1209: 1207: 1204: 1202: 1199: 1197: 1194: 1192: 1189: 1187: 1184: 1182: 1179: 1177: 1174: 1172: 1169: 1167: 1164: 1162: 1159: 1157: 1154: 1152: 1149: 1147: 1144: 1142: 1139: 1138: 1136: 1132: 1126: 1123: 1121: 1118: 1116: 1113: 1110: 1106: 1103: 1101: 1098: 1096: 1093: 1091: 1088: 1086: 1085:Structuralism 1083: 1081: 1078: 1076: 1073: 1071: 1068: 1066: 1063: 1061: 1058: 1056: 1053: 1051: 1048: 1046: 1043: 1041: 1038: 1036: 1033: 1031: 1028: 1026: 1023: 1021: 1018: 1016: 1013: 1011: 1010:Descriptivism 1008: 1006: 1003: 1001: 998: 996: 993: 991: 990:Contrastivism 988: 986: 983: 981: 978: 977: 975: 973: 969: 963: 960: 958: 955: 953: 950: 948: 945: 943: 940: 938: 935: 933: 930: 928: 925: 923: 920: 918: 915: 913: 910: 908: 905: 903: 900: 898: 895: 893: 890: 888: 885: 883: 880: 878: 875: 873: 870: 868: 865: 863: 860: 858: 855: 853: 850: 848: 845: 843: 840: 838: 835: 833: 830: 828: 825: 823: 820: 818: 815: 813: 810: 808: 805: 803: 800: 798: 795: 793: 790: 788: 785: 783: 780: 778: 775: 773: 770: 768: 765: 763: 760: 758: 755: 753: 750: 748: 745: 743: 740: 738: 735: 733: 730: 728: 725: 724: 722: 720: 716: 712: 707: 703: 696: 691: 689: 684: 682: 677: 676: 673: 665: 659: 651: 646: 642: 638: 634: 630: 626: 622: 617: 612: 609:(3): B1–B12. 608: 604: 599: 596: 592: 589: 586: 583: 580: 576: 575:Kripke, Saul. 573: 570: 566: 563: 559: 555: 552: 551: 540:, p. 165 539: 534: 528:, p. 212 527: 522: 515: 509: 501: 497: 493: 489: 485: 481: 477: 473: 466: 459: 455: 451: 445: 438: 432: 430: 422: 418: 413: 411: 404: 399: 397: 389: 383: 376: 370: 366: 356: 353: 351: 348: 347: 343: 332: 325: 323: 320:known today. 318: 314: 309: 306: 302: 300: 296: 290: 288: 283: 271: 267: 263: 259: 255: 252: 248: 244: 240: 239: 238: 230: 228: 225: 221: 217: 211: 209: 201: 197: 193: 189: 185: 181: 178: 174: 173: 172: 169: 167: 163: 162:Gottlob Frege 159: 155: 152: 142: 140: 135: 130: 127: 122: 117: 113: 111: 107: 103: 99: 98: 87: 85: 81: 80:Hilary Putnam 78:. Kripke and 77: 72: 65: 61: 58: 54: 50: 46: 45: 44: 42: 38: 34: 30: 19: 1418: 1408: 1398: 1388: 1378: 1368: 1358: 1348: 1328: 1318: 1308: 1298: 1288: 1270: 1211:Metalanguage 1206:Logical form 1161:Truth-bearer 1120:Unilalianism 1030:Expressivism 979: 857:Wittgenstein 802:von Humboldt 719:Philosophers 649: 606: 602: 594: 578: 568: 561: 533: 521: 513: 508: 475: 471: 465: 457: 453: 449: 444: 436: 420: 387: 382: 374: 369: 313:Gareth Evans 310: 303: 291: 282:Gareth Evans 280: 261: 257: 249:in 1972 and 242: 236: 212: 205: 199: 191: 176: 170: 148: 134:Gareth Evans 131: 125: 120: 118: 114: 95: 93: 84:natural kind 73: 69: 64:causal chain 41:natural kind 37:proper names 28: 26: 1455:Linguistics 1420:Limited Inc 1340:On Denoting 1166:Proposition 817:de Saussure 782:Ibn Khaldun 652:. Stanford. 478:: 187–225. 299:John Searle 266:David Lewis 251:Saul Kripke 53:Saul Kripke 1530:Categories 1515:Discussion 1510:Task Force 1460:Pragmatics 1251:Speech act 1181:Categories 1095:Symbiosism 1050:Nominalism 962:Watzlawick 842:Bloomfield 762:Chrysippus 567:Evans, G. 548:References 317:Marco Polo 287:photograph 233:Variations 220:Twin Earth 145:Motivation 1546:Causality 1492:Semiotics 1480:Semantics 1330:Alciphron 1266:Statement 1201:Intension 1141:Ambiguity 1020:Dramatism 1000:Cratylism 752:Eubulides 747:Aristotle 727:Confucius 658:cite book 611:CiteSeerX 603:Cognition 593:. (1981) 554:Evans, G. 492:0309-7013 47:a name's 33:referents 1505:Category 1465:Rhetoric 1290:Cratylus 1261:Sentence 1236:Property 1156:Language 1134:Concepts 972:Theories 937:Strawson 922:Davidson 912:Hintikka 907:Anscombe 852:Vygotsky 807:Mauthner 777:Averroes 767:Zhuangzi 757:Diodorus 737:Cratylus 641:15074526 633:15019555 328:See also 295:aardvark 224:Swampman 49:referent 1272:more... 1176:Concept 917:Dummett 892:Gadamer 887:Chomsky 872:Derrida 862:Russell 847:Bergson 832:Tillich 792:Leibniz 732:Gorgias 500:4106912 200:meaning 151:logical 106:Russell 86:terms. 1424:(1988) 1414:(1982) 1404:(1980) 1394:(1967) 1384:(1953) 1374:(1951) 1364:(1936) 1354:(1921) 1344:(1905) 1334:(1732) 1324:(1668) 1314:(1666) 1304:(1660) 1294:(n.d.) 1256:Symbol 957:Searle 947:Putnam 897:Kripke 882:Austin 867:Carnap 812:Ricœur 797:Herder 787:Hobbes 639:  631:  613:  577:1980. 560:, ed. 498:  490:  260:(also 39:, and 1536:Names 1282:Works 1191:Class 952:Lewis 942:Quine 927:Grice 877:Whorf 837:Sapir 822:Frege 772:Xunzi 742:Plato 637:S2CID 496:JSTOR 361:Notes 192:could 1241:Sign 1146:Cant 932:Ryle 902:Ayer 827:Boas 664:link 629:PMID 488:ISSN 256:The 241:The 222:and 121:they 1186:Set 621:doi 480:doi 141:). 126:was 1532:: 1342:" 660:}} 656:{{ 635:. 627:. 619:. 607:92 605:. 494:. 486:. 476:47 474:. 454:62 452:, 428:^ 419:, 409:^ 395:^ 272:.) 229:. 177:no 27:A 1338:" 1111:) 1107:( 694:e 687:t 680:v 666:) 643:. 623:: 502:. 482:: 66:. 20:)

Index

Causal-historical theory of reference
referents
proper names
natural kind
referent
Saul Kripke
rigid designator
causal chain
Keith Donnellan
Hilary Putnam
natural kind
Naming and Necessity
descriptive theory of names
Russell
definite descriptions
Gareth Evans
Twin Earth thought experiment
logical
contradictions
definite descriptions
Gottlob Frege
On Sense and Reference
Christopher Columbus
rigid designator
possible worlds
semantic externalism
Twin Earth
Swampman
thought experiments
Keith Donnellan

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.