Knowledge

Novikov self-consistency principle

Source đź“ť

160:(where Thorne taught), arrived at a solution to the problem, that lays out the same elements as the solution Feynman and Wheeler termed the "glancing blow" solution, to evade inconsistencies arising from causality loops. In the revised scenario, the ball from the future emerges at a different angle than the one that generates the paradox, and delivers its younger self a glancing blow instead of knocking it completely away from the wormhole. This blow alters its trajectory by just the right degree, meaning it will travel back in time with the angle required to deliver its younger self the necessary glancing blow. Echeverria and Klinkhammer actually found that there was more than one self-consistent solution, with slightly different angles for the glancing blow in each situation. Later analysis by Thorne and 310:
result. Given an appropriate negative delay something else is possible: the result of each iteration of the function is brought back in time to serve as the "first" approximation. As soon as the machine is activated, a so-called "fixed-point" of F, an input which produces an identical output, usually signaling a perfect answer, appears (by an extraordinary coincidence!) immediately and steadily. If the iteration does not converge, that is, if F has no fixed point, the computer outputs and inputs will shut down or hover in an unlikely intermediate state.
258:
younger self if you travel back in time. You can coexist, take yourself out for a beer, celebrate your birthday together, but somehow circumstances will dictate that you cannot behave in a way that leads to a paradox in time. Novikov supports this point of view with another argument: physics already restricts your free will every day. You may will yourself to fly or to walk through a concrete wall, but gravity and condensed-matter physics dictate that you cannot. Why, Novikov asks, is the consistency restriction placed on a time traveler any different?
121: 249:
change the past. Such change is incompatible with the principle of self-consistency. Consequently, any being who went through a wormhole and tried to change the past would be prevented by physical law from making the change; i.e., the "free will" of the being would be constrained. Although this constraint has a more global character than constraints on free will that follow from the standard, local laws of physics, it is not obvious to us that this constraint is more severe than those imposed by standard physical law.
225:, a self-evident truth that cannot possibly be false. However, the Novikov self-consistency principle is intended to go beyond just the statement that history must be consistent, making the additional nontrivial assumption that the universe obeys the same local laws of physics in situations involving time travel that it does in regions of space-time that lack closed timelike curves. This is clarified in the above-mentioned "Cauchy problem in spacetimes with closed timelike curves", where the authors write: 129: 230:
self-consistency is intended to rule out such behavior. It insists that local physics is governed by the same types of physical laws as we deal with in the absence of CTCs: the laws that entail self-consistent single valuedness for the fields. In essence, the principle of self-consistency is a principle of no new physics. If one is inclined from the outset to ignore or discount the possibility of new physics, then one will regard self-consistency as a trivial principle.
348:, even if it is not built up by quantum systems. The authors conclude that hence, Deutsch's condition is not specific to quantum physics, nor does it depend on the quantum nature of a physical system so that it can be fulfilled. In consequence, Tolksdorf and Verch argue that Deutsch's condition is not sufficiently specific to allow statements about time travel scenarios or their hypothetical realization by quantum physics. 197:, such a sum over histories produces unique, self-consistent probabilities for the outcomes of all sets of subsequent measurements. ... We suspect, more generally, that for any quantum system in a classical wormhole spacetime with a stable Cauchy horizon, the sum over all self-consistent histories will give unique, self-consistent probabilities for the outcomes of all sets of measurements that one might choose to make. 559:(1979), Novikov's comment on the issue is rendered by translator M. M. Basko as "The close of time curves does not necessarily imply a violation of causality, since the events along such a closed line may be all 'self-adjusted'—they all affect one another through the closed cycle and follow one another in a self-consistent way." 180:
initial trajectory they analyzed—can be seen as problematic, since classically there seems to be no way to decide which extension the laws of physics will choose. To get around this difficulty, Thorne and Klinkhammer analyzed the billiard ball scenario using quantum mechanics, performing a quantum-mechanical sum over histories (
88:
argued that they cannot entail this type of causality violation: events on a CTC are already guaranteed to be self-consistent, Novikov argued; they influence each other around a closed curve in a self-adjusted, cyclical, self-consistent way. The other authors recently have arrived at the same viewpoint.
451:, centers heavily on the question whether the past can be changed or not. Some of the characters in the plot are driven to change it, whereas others, who have already tried doing so in vain, have resigned themselves to come to the conclusion that the Novikov self-consistency principle seemingly applies. 335:
problems in polynomial time. Deutsch shows that quantum computation with a negative delay—backwards time travel—produces only self-consistent solutions, and the chronology-violating region imposes constraints that are not apparent through classical reasoning. Researchers published in 2014
309:
Make a computing box that accepts an input, which represents an approximate solution to some problem, and produces an output that is an improved approximation. Conventionally you would apply such a computation repeatedly a finite number of times, and then settle for the better, but still approximate,
257:
According to the consistency conjecture, any complex interpersonal interactions must work themselves out self-consistently so that there is no paradox. That is the resolution. This means, if taken literally, that if time machines exist, there can be no free will. You cannot will yourself to kill your
87:
The only type of causality violation that the authors would find unacceptable is that embodied in the science-fiction concept of going backward in time and killing one's younger self ("changing the past"). Some years ago one of us (Novikov) briefly considered the possibility that CTCs might exist and
179:
Even if self-consistent extensions can be found for arbitrary initial conditions outside the Cauchy horizon, the finding that there can be multiple distinct self-consistent extensions for the same initial condition—indeed, Echeverria et al. found an infinite number of consistent extensions for every
116:
could lead to closed timelike curves, and unlike previous CTC-containing solutions, it did not require unrealistic conditions for the universe as a whole. After discussions with the lead author of the 1990 paper, John Friedman, they convinced themselves that time travel need not lead to unresolvable
171:
initial conditions for the billiard ball for which there were no self-consistent extensions, but were unable to do so. Thus, it is plausible that there exist self-consistent extensions for every possible initial trajectory, although this has not been proven. This only applies to initial conditions
188:
The simplest way to impose the principle of self-consistency in quantum mechanics (in a classical space-time) is by a sum-over-histories formulation in which one includes all those, and only those, histories that are self-consistent. It turns out that, at least formally (modulo such issues as the
248:
If CTCs are allowed, and if the above vision of theoretical physics' accommodation with them turns out to be more or less correct, then what will this imply about the philosophical notion of free will for humans and other intelligent beings? It certainly will imply that intelligent beings cannot
472:
follows the Novikov self-consistency principle. Two of the main characters can travel backwards in time by jumping into a pond, but they are unable to change anything in the past. All of their actions become part of history, and they actually end up causing the tragic events they were trying to
229:
That the principle of self-consistency is not totally tautological becomes clear when one considers the following alternative: The laws of physics might permit CTCs; and when CTCs occur, they might trigger new kinds of local physics which we have not previously met. ... The principle of
336:
a simulation in which they claim to have validated Deutsch's model with photons. However, it was shown in an article by Tolksdorf and Verch that Deutsch's self-consistency condition can be fulfilled to arbitrary precision in any quantum system described according to relativistic
148:
at an angle such that, if it continues along its path, it will exit in the past at just the right angle to collide with its earlier self, knocking it off track and preventing it from entering the wormhole in the first place. Thorne would refer to this scenario as
112:, and Ulvi Yurtsever, who in 1988 had stirred up renewed interest in the subject of time travel in general relativity with their paper "Wormholes, Time Machines, and the Weak Energy Condition", which showed that a new general relativity solution known as a 99:
This principle allows one to build a local solution to the equations of physics only if that local solution can be extended to a part of a (not necessarily unique) global solution, which is well defined throughout the nonsingular regions of the space-time.
79:. Novikov discussed the possibility of closed timelike curves (CTCs) in books he wrote in 1975 and 1983, offering the opinion that only self-consistent trips back in time would be permitted. In a 1990 paper by Novikov and several others, " 418:: In Eliezer Yudkowsky's exposition on rationality, framed as a piece of Harry Potter fanfiction, Harry attempts to use his Time Turner to influence the past and comes to the conclusion that the Novikov self-consistency principle applies. 239:
The assumptions of the self-consistency principle can be extended to hypothetical scenarios involving intelligent time travelers as well as unintelligent objects such as billiard balls. The authors of "Cauchy problem in spacetimes with
293:
and relies upon the self-consistency principle to force the sent result to be correct, provided the machine can reliably receive information from the future and provided the algorithm and the underlying mechanism are
184:) using only the consistent extensions, and found that this resulted in a well-defined probability for each consistent extension. The authors of "Cauchy problem in spacetimes with closed timelike curves" write: 439:
is largely based on the notion that the possibility of time travel tempts the characters to try change the past, which only leads them to cause the events they were trying to prevent in the first place.
340:
even on spacetimes which do not admit closed timelike curves, casting doubts on whether Deutsch's model is really characteristic of quantum processes simulating closed timelike curves in the sense of
176:. This could mean that the Novikov self-consistency principle does not actually place any constraints on systems outside of the region of space-time where time travel is possible, only inside it. 281:, is a hypothetical system of computation that exploits the Novikov self-consistency principle to compute answers much faster than possible with the standard model of 923: 1122:
Ringbauer, Martin; Broome, Matthew A.; Myers, Casey R.; White, Andrew G.; Ralph, Timothy C. (19 June 2014). "Experimental simulation of closed timelike curves".
167:
Echeverria, Klinkhammer, and Thorne published a paper discussing these results in 1991; in addition, they reported that they had tried to see if they could find
206:
The Novikov consistency principle assumes certain conditions about what sort of time travel is possible. Specifically, it assumes either that there is only one
1405: 1301: 1401: 1297: 344:. In a later article, the same authors show that Deutsch's CTC fixed point condition can also be fulfilled in any system subject to the laws of classical 1309: 1321: 1397: 1325: 1293: 1409: 1317: 1305: 361: 1313: 164:
illustrated that for certain initial trajectories of the billiard ball, there could actually be an infinite number of self-consistent solutions.
140:
wrote them a letter arguing that one could avoid the issue of free will by employing a potentially paradoxical thought experiment involving a
1183:
Tolksdorf, Juergen; Verch, Rainer (2018). "Quantum physics, fields and closed timelike curves: The D-CTC condition in quantum field theory".
1236:
Tolksdorf, Juergen; Verch, Rainer (2021). "The D-CTC condition is generically fulfilled in classical (non-quantum) statistical systems".
459:(2019): A video game involving time travel which does not follow the principle, causing a game over if the player experiments to test it. 414: 298:. An incorrect result or no result can still be produced if the time travel mechanism or algorithm are not guaranteed to be accurate. 1038: 663: 394: 97:
the only solutions to the laws of physics that can occur locally in the real Universe are those which are globally self-consistent.
1468: 697: 55:. The principle asserts that if an event exists that would cause a paradox or any "change" to the past whatsoever, then the 927: 574:
Friedman, John; Michael Morris; Igor Novikov; Fernando Echeverria; Gunnar Klinkhammer; Kip Thorne; Ulvi Yurtsever (1990).
221:
Given these assumptions, the constraint that time travel must not lead to inconsistent outcomes could be seen merely as a
364:
and path integrals. In particular, the path integral is over single-valued fields, leading to self-consistent histories.
1105: 903: 157: 878: 853: 735: 518: 493: 282: 1332:(27 January 2011). "Closed Timelike Curves via Postselection: Theory and Experimental Test of Consistency". 498: 1510: 726: 508: 389:. The anomaly returns and sends it back into the present, before it has a chance to affect the outcome. 374: 211: 181: 40: 542:
See note 10 on p. 42 of Friedman et al., "Cauchy problem in space-times with closed timelike curves"
144:
sent back in time through a wormhole. In Polchinski's scenario, the billiard ball is fired into the
468: 846:
Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes
630: 324: 150: 109: 952: 689: 503: 386: 1329: 345: 241: 72: 52: 1505: 1500: 1431: 1351: 1255: 1202: 1141: 1081: 1014: 999: 964: 805: 764: 639: 587: 448: 337: 156:
Upon considering the scenario, Fernando Echeverria and Gunnar Klinkhammer, two students at
71:
Physicists have long known that some solutions to the theory of general relativity contain
16:
Assertion that time-travel paradoxes are impossible, as paradox-causing events cannot occur
189:
convergence of the sum), for every choice of the billiard ball's initial, nonrelativistic
8: 622: 513: 488: 422: 295: 113: 1480: 1435: 1355: 1259: 1206: 1145: 1085: 1018: 968: 809: 768: 643: 591: 1447: 1421: 1375: 1341: 1271: 1245: 1218: 1192: 1165: 1131: 1097: 1071: 682: 341: 48: 1485: 1026: 1475:
From wormhole to time machine: Comments on Hawking's Chronology Protection Conjecture
1367: 1275: 1222: 1157: 1030: 980: 899: 874: 849: 821: 794:"Billiard balls in wormhole spacetimes with closed timelike curves: Classical theory" 731: 693: 655: 603: 573: 222: 215: 137: 1451: 1412:(2011). "The quantum mechanics of time travel through post-selected teleportation". 1379: 1169: 120: 1439: 1363: 1359: 1263: 1210: 1149: 1089: 1022: 972: 813: 772: 647: 595: 463: 435: 302: 44: 1101: 651: 76: 1443: 1267: 328: 286: 194: 173: 172:
outside of the chronology-violating region of spacetime, which is bounded by a
161: 80: 1214: 1056: 777: 752: 331:
later extended this result to show that the model could also be used to solve
1494: 976: 817: 599: 443: 320: 190: 141: 128: 1371: 1161: 1093: 1034: 984: 919: 896:
Cosmic Catastrophes: Exploding Stars, Black Holes, and Mapping the Universe
825: 793: 659: 607: 575: 278: 60: 378:(1980): A science-fiction time-travel movie in which the aircraft carrier 523: 483: 455: 406: 402:
explores the interplay between free will and self-consistent time-travel.
323:
showed in 1991 that this model of computation could solve NP problems in
290: 56: 28: 1057:"Closed Timelike Curves Make Quantum and Classical Computing Equivalent" 1474: 1393: 1289: 1153: 871:
Time Machines: Time Travel in Physics, Metaphysics, and Science Fiction
721: 399: 379: 357: 274: 207: 105: 791: 410:(2009): Cited by Makise Kurisu during her presentation on time travel. 427: 268: 253:
Similarly, physicist and astronomer J. Craig Wheeler concludes that:
210:, or that any alternative timelines (such as those postulated by the 36: 1392: 1288: 1250: 1197: 1136: 753:"Classical Electrodynamics in Terms of Direct Interparticle Action" 145: 1426: 1346: 1076: 620: 332: 117:
paradoxes, regardless of the object sent through the wormhole.
83:
in spacetimes with closed timelike curves", the authors state:
1111:
from the original on 2022-10-09 – via scottaaronson.com.
1044:
from the original on 2022-10-09 – via scottaaronson.com.
898:(2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 294–295. 43:
in the mid-1980s. Novikov intended it to solve the problem of
1477:, which also addresses the Novikov self-consistency principle 792:
Echeverria, Fernando; Gunnar Klinkhammer; Kip Thorne (1991).
289:. In this system, a computer sends a result of a computation 244:" commented on the issue in the paper's conclusion, writing: 59:
of that event is zero. It would thus be impossible to create
314: 47:, which is theoretically permitted in certain solutions of 576:"Cauchy problem in spacetimes with closed timelike curves" 1121: 623:"Wormholes, Time Machines, and the Weak Energy Condition" 684:
Black Holes and Time Warps: Einstein's Outrageous Legacy
621:
Thorne, Kip; Michael Morris; Ulvi Yurtsever (1988).
555:(1983), which was a translation of his Russian book 681: 234: 1115: 385:passes through a wormhole back to the eve of the 1492: 1481:Einstein Physics prevent paradoxical time travel 1054: 356:An alternative proposal was later presented by 1235: 1182: 953:"Quantum mechanics near closed timelike lines" 946: 944: 873:. American Institute of Physics. p. 508. 750: 104:Among the co-authors of this 1990 paper were 941: 716: 714: 712: 415:Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality 1469:Notion of the Past & Can We Change It? 569: 567: 565: 1425: 1345: 1249: 1196: 1135: 1075: 776: 673: 315:Quantum computation with a negative delay 997: 839: 837: 835: 751:Wheeler, John; Feynman, Richard (1949). 709: 127: 119: 1055:Aaronson, Scott; Watrous, John (2009). 950: 918: 893: 562: 351: 132:Echeverria and Klinkhammer's resolution 1493: 1185:Communications in Mathematical Physics 843: 720: 679: 868: 832: 395:The Merchant and the Alchemist's Gate 367: 426:: A science-fiction novel series by 91:We shall embody this viewpoint in a 25:Novikov self-consistency conjecture 13: 1064:Proceedings of the Royal Society A 262: 21:Novikov self-consistency principle 14: 1522: 1462: 1027:10.1038/scientificamerican0308-62 1000:"The Limits of Quantum Computers" 669:from the original on 2022-10-09. 519:Quantum mechanics of time travel 494:Chronology protection conjecture 1386: 1282: 1229: 1176: 1048: 991: 912: 887: 862: 387:Japanese attack on Pearl Harbor 235:Implications for time travelers 51:that contain what are known as 39:developed by Russian physicist 1486:Time Travel and Modern Physics 1364:10.1103/PhysRevLett.106.040403 998:Aaronson, Scott (March 2008). 785: 744: 614: 545: 536: 201: 136:By way of response, physicist 93:principle of self-consistency, 33:law of conservation of history 1: 529: 499:Cosmic censorship hypothesis 7: 924:"Time Travel and Computing" 848:. Oxford University Press. 652:10.1103/PhysRevLett.61.1446 477: 473:prevent in the first place. 430:that applies the principle. 305:algorithm. Moravec states: 273:Time-loop logic, coined by 10: 1527: 1444:10.1103/PhysRevD.84.025007 1268:10.1007/s10701-021-00496-z 894:Wheeler, J. Craig (2007). 727:Black Holes and Time Warps 509:Many-worlds interpretation 266: 212:many-worlds interpretation 66: 1215:10.1007/s00220-017-2943-5 778:10.1103/RevModPhys.21.425 757:Reviews of Modern Physics 688:. W. W. Norton. pp.  553:Evolution of the Universe 41:Igor Dmitriyevich Novikov 977:10.1103/PhysRevD.44.3197 818:10.1103/PhysRevD.44.1077 600:10.1103/PhysRevD.42.1915 447:(2016): A video game by 283:computational complexity 45:paradoxes in time travel 1334:Physical Review Letters 951:Deutsch, David (1991). 869:Nahin, Paul J. (1999). 680:Thorne, Kip S. (1994). 631:Physical Review Letters 551:On p. 169 of Novikov's 462:All time travel in the 301:A simple example is an 75:—for example the 1330:Steinberg, Aephraim M. 1238:Foundations of Physics 1094:10.1098/rspa.2008.0350 504:The chicken or the egg 312: 291:backwards through time 260: 251: 242:closed timelike curves 232: 218:) are not accessible. 199: 133: 125: 124:"Polchinski's paradox" 102: 73:closed timelike curves 53:closed timelike curves 1406:Giovannetti, Vittorio 1302:Giovannetti, Vittorio 1124:Nature Communications 844:Earman, John (1995). 704:Polchinski's paradox. 557:Evolyutsiya VselennoÄ­ 346:statistical mechanics 307: 255: 246: 227: 186: 131: 123: 85: 449:Remedy Entertainment 352:Lloyd's prescription 338:quantum field theory 151:Polchinski's paradox 114:traversable wormhole 23:, also known as the 1471:– speech by Novikov 1436:2011PhRvD..84b5007L 1402:Garcia-Patron, Raul 1356:2011PhRvL.106d0403L 1298:Garcia-Patron, Raul 1260:2021FoPh...51...93T 1207:2018CMaPh.357..319T 1146:2014NatCo...5.4145R 1086:2009RSPSA.465..631A 1019:2008SciAm.298c..62A 1007:Scientific American 969:1991PhRvD..44.3197D 810:1991PhRvD..44.1077E 769:1949RvMP...21..425W 644:1988PhRvL..61.1446M 592:1990PhRvD..42.1915F 514:Grandfather paradox 489:Causality (physics) 433:The Netflix series 375:The Final Countdown 1511:Temporal paradoxes 1310:Pirandola, Stefano 1154:10.1038/ncomms5145 368:In popular culture 342:general relativity 134: 126: 95:which states that 49:general relativity 1414:Physical Review D 1322:Soudagar, Yasaman 1070:(2102): 631–647. 963:(10): 3197–3217. 957:Physical Review D 798:Physical Review D 699:978-0-393-31276-8 638:(13): 1446–1449. 580:Physical Review D 216:quantum mechanics 138:Joseph Polchinski 1518: 1456: 1455: 1429: 1398:Maccone, Lorenzo 1390: 1384: 1383: 1349: 1326:Shalm, Lynden K. 1294:Maccone, Lorenzo 1286: 1280: 1279: 1253: 1233: 1227: 1226: 1200: 1180: 1174: 1173: 1139: 1119: 1113: 1112: 1110: 1079: 1061: 1052: 1046: 1045: 1043: 1004: 995: 989: 988: 948: 939: 938: 936: 935: 926:. Archived from 916: 910: 909: 891: 885: 884: 866: 860: 859: 841: 830: 829: 804:(4): 1077–1099. 789: 783: 782: 780: 748: 742: 741: 730:. W. W. Norton. 718: 707: 706: 687: 677: 671: 670: 668: 627: 618: 612: 611: 586:(6): 1915–1930. 571: 560: 549: 543: 540: 466:original series 464:Hallmark Channel 303:iterative method 296:formally correct 1526: 1525: 1521: 1520: 1519: 1517: 1516: 1515: 1491: 1490: 1465: 1460: 1459: 1410:Shikano, Yutaka 1391: 1387: 1318:Darabi, Ardavan 1306:Shikano, Yutaka 1287: 1283: 1234: 1230: 1181: 1177: 1120: 1116: 1108: 1059: 1053: 1049: 1041: 1002: 996: 992: 949: 942: 933: 931: 917: 913: 906: 892: 888: 881: 867: 863: 856: 842: 833: 790: 786: 749: 745: 738: 719: 710: 700: 678: 674: 666: 625: 619: 615: 572: 563: 550: 546: 541: 537: 532: 480: 370: 354: 325:polynomial time 317: 287:Turing machines 271: 265: 263:Time-loop logic 237: 204: 69: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1524: 1514: 1513: 1508: 1503: 1489: 1488: 1483: 1478: 1472: 1464: 1463:External links 1461: 1458: 1457: 1385: 1314:Rozema, Lee A. 1281: 1228: 1191:(1): 319–351. 1175: 1114: 1047: 990: 940: 911: 905:978-0521857147 904: 886: 879: 861: 854: 831: 784: 763:(3): 425–433. 743: 736: 722:Thorne, Kip S. 708: 698: 672: 613: 561: 544: 534: 533: 531: 528: 527: 526: 521: 516: 511: 506: 501: 496: 491: 486: 479: 476: 475: 474: 460: 452: 440: 431: 419: 411: 403: 390: 369: 366: 362:post-selection 353: 350: 329:Scott Aaronson 316: 313: 267:Main article: 264: 261: 236: 233: 203: 200: 195:Cauchy horizon 174:Cauchy horizon 162:Robert Forward 81:Cauchy problem 68: 65: 61:time paradoxes 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1523: 1512: 1509: 1507: 1504: 1502: 1499: 1498: 1496: 1487: 1484: 1482: 1479: 1476: 1473: 1470: 1467: 1466: 1453: 1449: 1445: 1441: 1437: 1433: 1428: 1423: 1420:(2): 025007. 1419: 1415: 1411: 1407: 1403: 1399: 1395: 1389: 1381: 1377: 1373: 1369: 1365: 1361: 1357: 1353: 1348: 1343: 1340:(4): 040403. 1339: 1335: 1331: 1327: 1323: 1319: 1315: 1311: 1307: 1303: 1299: 1295: 1291: 1285: 1277: 1273: 1269: 1265: 1261: 1257: 1252: 1247: 1243: 1239: 1232: 1224: 1220: 1216: 1212: 1208: 1204: 1199: 1194: 1190: 1186: 1179: 1171: 1167: 1163: 1159: 1155: 1151: 1147: 1143: 1138: 1133: 1129: 1125: 1118: 1107: 1103: 1099: 1095: 1091: 1087: 1083: 1078: 1073: 1069: 1065: 1058: 1051: 1040: 1036: 1032: 1028: 1024: 1020: 1016: 1012: 1008: 1001: 994: 986: 982: 978: 974: 970: 966: 962: 958: 954: 947: 945: 930:on 2009-01-29 929: 925: 921: 920:Moravec, Hans 915: 907: 901: 897: 890: 882: 880:0-387-98571-9 876: 872: 865: 857: 855:0-19-509591-X 851: 847: 840: 838: 836: 827: 823: 819: 815: 811: 807: 803: 799: 795: 788: 779: 774: 770: 766: 762: 758: 754: 747: 739: 737:0-393-31276-3 733: 729: 728: 723: 717: 715: 713: 705: 701: 695: 691: 686: 685: 676: 665: 661: 657: 653: 649: 645: 641: 637: 633: 632: 624: 617: 609: 605: 601: 597: 593: 589: 585: 581: 577: 570: 568: 566: 558: 554: 548: 539: 535: 525: 522: 520: 517: 515: 512: 510: 507: 505: 502: 500: 497: 495: 492: 490: 487: 485: 482: 481: 471: 470: 465: 461: 458: 457: 453: 450: 446: 445: 444:Quantum Break 441: 438: 437: 432: 429: 425: 424: 420: 417: 416: 412: 409: 408: 404: 401: 397: 396: 391: 388: 384: 383: 377: 376: 372: 371: 365: 363: 359: 349: 347: 343: 339: 334: 330: 326: 322: 321:David Deutsch 311: 306: 304: 299: 297: 292: 288: 284: 280: 277:and futurist 276: 270: 259: 254: 250: 245: 243: 231: 226: 224: 219: 217: 213: 209: 198: 196: 192: 191:wave function 185: 183: 182:path integral 177: 175: 170: 165: 163: 159: 154: 152: 147: 143: 142:billiard ball 139: 130: 122: 118: 115: 111: 107: 101: 98: 94: 89: 84: 82: 78: 74: 64: 62: 58: 54: 50: 46: 42: 38: 34: 30: 26: 22: 1417: 1413: 1388: 1337: 1333: 1284: 1241: 1237: 1231: 1188: 1184: 1178: 1127: 1123: 1117: 1067: 1063: 1050: 1013:(3): 68–69. 1010: 1006: 993: 960: 956: 932:. Retrieved 928:the original 914: 895: 889: 870: 864: 845: 801: 797: 787: 760: 756: 746: 725: 703: 683: 675: 635: 629: 616: 583: 579: 556: 552: 547: 538: 469:The Way Home 467: 454: 442: 434: 421: 413: 405: 393: 381: 373: 355: 318: 308: 300: 279:Hans Moravec 272: 256: 252: 247: 238: 228: 220: 205: 187: 178: 168: 166: 155: 135: 103: 96: 92: 90: 86: 77:Gödel metric 70: 32: 24: 20: 18: 1506:Conjectures 1501:Time travel 1394:Lloyd, Seth 1290:Lloyd, Seth 524:Time viewer 484:Causal loop 456:Outer Wilds 407:Steins;Gate 360:based upon 202:Assumptions 193:before the 153:" in 1994. 110:Mike Morris 57:probability 29:Larry Niven 1495:Categories 1251:1912.02301 1244:(93): 93. 1198:1609.01496 1137:1501.05014 934:2008-07-28 530:References 423:Orthogonal 400:Ted Chiang 398:(2007) by 392:The story 358:Seth Lloyd 319:Physicist 275:roboticist 106:Kip Thorne 1427:1007.2615 1347:1005.2219 1276:208637445 1223:253751446 1077:0808.2669 428:Greg Egan 269:Time loop 223:tautology 37:principle 1452:15972766 1380:18442086 1372:21405310 1170:12779043 1162:24942489 1130:: 4145. 1106:Archived 1039:Archived 1035:18357822 985:10013776 922:(1991). 826:10013968 724:(1994). 664:Archived 660:10038800 608:10013039 478:See also 208:timeline 146:wormhole 1432:Bibcode 1352:Bibcode 1256:Bibcode 1203:Bibcode 1142:Bibcode 1082:Bibcode 1015:Bibcode 965:Bibcode 806:Bibcode 765:Bibcode 640:Bibcode 588:Bibcode 158:Caltech 67:History 35:, is a 1450:  1378:  1370:  1274:  1221:  1168:  1160:  1102:745646 1100:  1033:  983:  902:  877:  852:  824:  734:  696:  658:  606:  382:Nimitz 333:PSPACE 327:, and 285:using 1448:S2CID 1422:arXiv 1376:S2CID 1342:arXiv 1272:S2CID 1246:arXiv 1219:S2CID 1193:arXiv 1166:S2CID 1132:arXiv 1109:(PDF) 1098:S2CID 1072:arXiv 1060:(PDF) 1042:(PDF) 1003:(PDF) 667:(PDF) 626:(PDF) 1368:PMID 1158:PMID 1031:PMID 981:PMID 900:ISBN 875:ISBN 850:ISBN 822:PMID 732:ISBN 694:ISBN 656:PMID 604:PMID 436:Dark 380:USS 27:and 19:The 1440:doi 1360:doi 1338:106 1264:doi 1211:doi 1189:357 1150:doi 1090:doi 1068:465 1023:doi 1011:298 973:doi 814:doi 773:doi 692:–. 690:510 648:doi 596:doi 214:of 169:any 31:'s 1497:: 1446:. 1438:. 1430:. 1418:84 1416:. 1408:; 1404:; 1400:; 1396:; 1374:. 1366:. 1358:. 1350:. 1336:. 1328:; 1324:; 1320:; 1316:; 1312:; 1308:; 1304:; 1300:; 1296:; 1292:; 1270:. 1262:. 1254:. 1242:51 1240:. 1217:. 1209:. 1201:. 1187:. 1164:. 1156:. 1148:. 1140:. 1126:. 1104:. 1096:. 1088:. 1080:. 1066:. 1062:. 1037:. 1029:. 1021:. 1009:. 1005:. 979:. 971:. 961:44 959:. 955:. 943:^ 834:^ 820:. 812:. 802:44 800:. 796:. 771:. 761:21 759:. 755:. 711:^ 702:. 662:. 654:. 646:. 636:61 634:. 628:. 602:. 594:. 584:42 582:. 578:. 564:^ 108:, 63:. 1454:. 1442:: 1434:: 1424:: 1382:. 1362:: 1354:: 1344:: 1278:. 1266:: 1258:: 1248:: 1225:. 1213:: 1205:: 1195:: 1172:. 1152:: 1144:: 1134:: 1128:5 1092:: 1084:: 1074:: 1025:: 1017:: 987:. 975:: 967:: 937:. 908:. 883:. 858:. 828:. 816:: 808:: 781:. 775:: 767:: 740:. 650:: 642:: 610:. 598:: 590:: 149:"

Index

Larry Niven
principle
Igor Dmitriyevich Novikov
paradoxes in time travel
general relativity
closed timelike curves
probability
time paradoxes
closed timelike curves
Gödel metric
Cauchy problem
Kip Thorne
Mike Morris
traversable wormhole


Joseph Polchinski
billiard ball
wormhole
Polchinski's paradox
Caltech
Robert Forward
Cauchy horizon
path integral
wave function
Cauchy horizon
timeline
many-worlds interpretation
quantum mechanics
tautology

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑