Knowledge

Performative utterance

Source đź“ť

340:
Skinner 'there is a sense in which we need to understand why a certain proposition has been put forward if we wish to understand the proposition itself'. He values agency over structure and stresses the importance of authorial intentions. Skinner therefore proposes to study historical sources in order to retrieve the convictions the author held, reflect on their coherence and investigate possible motives for the illocutionary act. This practical method seeks to deal with the blurred distinction between text and context and offer a meaningful way of interpreting historical reality.
375:. Additionally, according to Sedgwick, performative utterances can be 'transformative' performatives, which create an instant change of personal or environmental status, or 'promisory' performatives, which describe the world as it might be in the future. These categories are not exclusive, so an utterance may well have both qualities. As Sedgwick observes, performative utterances can be revoked, either by the person who uttered them ("I take back my promise"), or by some other party not immediately involved, like the state (for example, 323:
Performativity has a political aspect that consists in what Derrida has described as the breaking force, by which an utterance changes its context. Butler assigns an important role to what Austin has called infelicities and parasitic uses of language. Quotations, parodies and other deviations from official discourse can become instruments of power that affect society.
273:, it states that neither the meaning, nor the context of a text can be defined in its entirety. Instead of emphasizing linguistic rules, scholars within this strand stress that the performative utterance is intertwined with structures of power. Because a text inevitably changes a situation or discourse, the distinction between text and context is blurred. 176:
conditions have to be met (e.g. a person who pronounces a marriage must be authorized to do so). Besides the context, the performative utterance itself is unambiguous as well. The words of an illocutionary act have to be expressed in earnest; if not, Austin discards them as a parasitic use of language.
291:
holds with Austin and Searle that by illocutionary force, language itself can transform and effect. However, he criticizes the notion of 'felicity conditions' and the idea that the success of a performative utterance is determined by conventions. Derrida values the distinctiveness of every individual
231:
to its broader context, that is to say everything outside the text itself. The question whether a performative is separable from the situation it emerged in is relevant when one addresses for example the status of individual intentions or speech as a resource of power. There are two main theoretical
470:
In 1972 Jacques Derrida published the article 'Signature Événement Contexte', in which he criticises several aspects of Austin's theory on the performative utterance. The first English translation appeared in 1977 in the first volume of Glyph. In the second volume (1977) Searle published an article
339:
Skinner agrees with Derrida that contexts in their entirety are irretrievable but nevertheless states that there is a relevant context outside the text that can be described in a plausible way. Extensive research is required to relate historical texts to their contemporary discourses. According to
188:
tried to develop his own account of speech acts, suggesting that these acts are a form of rule-governed behaviour. On the one hand, Searle discerns rules that merely regulate language, such as referring and predicating. These rules account for the "propositional content" of sentences. On the other
175:
Every performative utterance has its own procedure and risks of failure that Austin calls 'infelicities'. He sees a sharp distinction between the individual text and the 'total speech act situation' surrounding it. According to Austin, in order to successfully perform an illocutionary act, certain
307:
Besides the consequential effects, the dissolution of the text-context divide is also caused by iterability. Due to the possibility of repetition, the intentions of an individual actor can never be fully present in a speech act. The core of a performative utterance is therefore not constituted by
260:
that sees performance as a repeatable ritual. The focus here is largely on individual sentences in the active first person voice, rather than on politics or discourse. The syntactical analyses are firmly anchored in analytical epistemology, as the distinction between the research object and its
322:
Notwithstanding such social restraints, Butler underscores the possibility of agency. The boundaries of a discourse need continuous re-demarcation and this is where speech can escape its constriction. The emphasis on the limits of what is allowed to be said also frames that what is silenced.
335:
developed classical and postmodern theories on performative texts into a concrete research method. Using Austin's vocabulary, he seeks to recover what historical authors were doing in writing their texts, which corresponds with the performance of illocutionary acts. According to Skinner,
232:
strands in research today. One emphasizes the predetermined conventions surrounding a performative utterance and the clear distinction between text and context. Another emphasizes the active construction of reality through spoken and written texts and is related to theories of
192:
This focus on effect implies a conscious actor and Searle assumes that language stems from an intrinsic intentionality of the mind. These intentions set the prerequisites for the performance of speech acts and Searle sets out to map their necessary and sufficient conditions.
157:. When, for instance, one uses the word "Go!" in order to command someone to leave the room then this utterance is part of the performance of a command; and the sentence, according to Austin, is neither true nor false; hence the sentence is a performative; – still, it is 189:
hand, he discerns rules that are constitutive in character and define behaviour (e.g. when making a promise). These rules are the conventions underlying performative utterances and they enable not only representation and expression, but also communication.
303:
According to Derrida, the effects caused by a performative text are in a sense also part of it. In this way, the distinction between a text and that what is outside it dissolves. For this reason it is pointless to try to define the context of a speech act.
255:
Early theories acknowledge that performance and text are both embedded in a system of rules and that the effects they can produce depend on convention and recurrence. In this sense, text is an instance of 'restored behaviour', a term introduced by
208:, if "the successful performance of the speech act is sufficient to bring about the fit between words and world, to make the propositional content true." Searle believes that this double direction of fit contrasts the simple word-to-world fit of 296:, because it has a specific effect in the particular situation in which it is performed. It is because of this effect or 'breaking force' that Derrida calls the possibility of repeating a text 'iterability', a word derived from Latin 59:
philosophical claim that the utterances always "describe" or "constate" something and are thus always true or false. After mentioning several examples of sentences which are not so used, and not truth-evaluable (among them
351:
and Robert Harnish claimed that performatives are successful only if recipients infer the intention behind the literal meaning, and that therefore the success of the performative act is determined by the receiving side.
403:). Such a writing form is claimed to be, in itself, a form of performance. It is said to more accurately reflect the fleeting and ephemeral nature of a performance, and the various tricks of memory and 315:
offers a political interpretation of the concept of the performative utterance. Power in the form of active censorship defines and regulates the domain of a certain discourse. Indebted to the work of
336:
philosophical ideas are intertwined with claims of power. Every text is an act of communication that positions itself in relation to the status quo it seeks to change.
154: 471:
called: 'Reiterating the differences: a reply to Derrida', in which he defended Austin's theories. Derrida responded with the essay 'Limited Inc a b c...', (1977).
147: 392: 603: 404: 153:; to utter an "explicit" performative sentence is to make explicit what act one is performing. However, there are also "implicit", "primitive", or 276:
Austin and Searle thought in terms of demarcated contexts and transparent intentions, two issues that in the 1970s led Searle into polemics with
1424: 209: 723: 269:
The second set of theories on performance and text diverged from the tradition represented by Austin and Searle. Bearing the stamp of
111:), the performance of which, again, would not normally be described as simply "saying" or "describing" something (cf. Austin 1962, 5). 1197: 107:
The uttering of a performative is, or is part of, the doing of a certain kind of action (Austin later deals with them under the name
168:
As Austin observes, the acts purported to be performed by performative utterances may be socially contested. For instance,
92:
true or false; and he calls such sentences "constatives". In contrast to them, Austin defines "performatives" as follows:
1065: 732: 214: 200:
that performatives are true or false just like constatives. Searle further claimed that performatives are what he calls
505: 319:, Butler expounds how subjects are produced by their context, because the possibilities of speech are predetermined. 84:
In order to define performatives, Austin refers to those sentences which conform to the old prejudice in that they
227:
Building on the notion of performative utterances, scholars have theorized on the relation of a spoken or written
1419: 1152: 104:; instead when something is wrong with them then they are "unhappy", while if nothing is wrong they are "happy". 1273: 1147: 806: 716: 925: 746: 811: 47: 1293: 955: 776: 146:
As Austin later notices himself, these examples belong (more or less strikingly) to what Austin calls,
1298: 1248: 1010: 899: 709: 1358: 1217: 796: 1353: 894: 204:; this is a technical notion of Searle's account: according to his conception, an utterance is a 165:
performative, for it does not make explicit that the act the speaker is performing is a command.
42:
which not only describe a given reality, but also change the social reality they are describing.
129:
take this woman to be my lawful wedded wife)" – as uttered in the course of a marriage ceremony.
1383: 1020: 995: 935: 834: 766: 368: 228: 39: 27: 1278: 1172: 1137: 1025: 1000: 844: 761: 308:
animating intentions, as Austin and Searle would have it, but by the structure of language.
1263: 1070: 849: 388: 252:, proving their methodological use for example in the interpretation of historical texts. 8: 1414: 1348: 1313: 1258: 1202: 1105: 1090: 1060: 1040: 1015: 884: 869: 646: 421: 1393: 1318: 1288: 1253: 1233: 1162: 1142: 1080: 1075: 985: 975: 960: 904: 655: 31: 701: 1373: 1328: 1308: 1268: 1207: 1177: 1157: 950: 879: 501: 441: 257: 241: 108: 73: 1378: 1303: 1192: 970: 691: 169: 644:
Bach, Kent; Harnish, Robert (August 1981). "Linguistic Communication and Speech".
1182: 1085: 980: 945: 400: 332: 316: 288: 281: 245: 1368: 1363: 1283: 1167: 1045: 940: 781: 451: 20: 1408: 1055: 1030: 864: 696: 436: 312: 270: 101: 65: 19:
For the broader philosophical and critical applications of the concept, see
1323: 1243: 1110: 990: 874: 854: 426: 416: 376: 360: 233: 52: 391:; they are used as a justification for an attempt to create a new form of 1238: 1212: 1095: 859: 786: 431: 396: 185: 61: 407:
that happen in the mind of the viewer during and after the performance.
1388: 1035: 801: 756: 751: 659: 446: 293: 277: 249: 72:
and "ethical" propositions), he introduces "performative" sentences or
69: 56: 633:. Vol. 1 regarding method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 172:, may be accepted to constitute a divorce by some, but not by others. 1187: 1005: 930: 909: 839: 791: 771: 348: 237: 139:"I give and bequeath my watch to my brother" – as occurring in a will 1100: 889: 372: 355: 240:. The ideas about performance and text have contributed to the 965: 97: 364: 142:"I bet you sixpence it will rain tomorrow" (Austin 1962, 5) 363:
argued that there are performative aspects to nearly all
125: 731: 88:
used to describe or constate something, and which thus
170:"I divorce you", said three times by a man to his wife 579:
Derrida, Jacques (1988). "Signature Event Context".
524:
Speech Acts, an essay in the philosophy of language
184:Building on Austin's thought, language philosopher 544:Intentionality, an essay in the philosophy of mind 1406: 1198:Segmented discourse representation theory (SDRT) 604:Excitable speech: A politics of the performative 16:Category of utterances in philosophy of language 624: 622: 620: 618: 616: 614: 574: 572: 570: 568: 717: 596: 594: 592: 590: 561:. New York: Taylor & Francis. p. 36. 537: 535: 533: 517: 515: 513: 492: 490: 488: 45:In a 1955 lecture series, later published as 356:Performativeness as non-dichotomous variable 643: 611: 565: 724: 710: 587: 530: 510: 485: 556: 326: 264: 261:context is not conceived as problematic. 672: 546:. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 526:. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 628: 578: 382: 1407: 600: 541: 521: 79: 1153:Discourse representation theory (DRT) 705: 343: 559:Performance Studies, an Introduction 222: 1425:Formal semantics (natural language) 1066:Quantificational variability effect 733:Formal semantics (natural language) 13: 196:Searle argued in his 1989 article 14: 1436: 685: 387:The above ideas have influenced 96:Performative utterances are not 666: 500:Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962. 1148:Combinatory categorial grammar 637: 550: 464: 179: 1: 926:Antecedent-contained deletion 692:'Performative' on Glottopedia 478: 7: 557:Schechner, Richard (2006). 498:How to Do Things with Words 410: 287:The postmodern philosopher 48:How to Do Things with Words 10: 1441: 807:Syntax–semantics interface 155:"inexplicit" performatives 18: 1341: 1299:Question under discussion 1249:Conversational scoreboard 1226: 1130: 1123: 1026:Intersective modification 1011:Homogeneity (linguistics) 918: 827: 820: 739: 629:Skinner, Quentin (2003). 1359:Distributional semantics 677:. Duke University Press. 542:Searle, John R. (1983). 522:Searle, John R. (1974). 457: 379:vows pre-legalisation). 119:Austin gives are these: 115:The initial examples of 1354:Computational semantics 1091:Subsective modification 895:Propositional attitudes 601:Butler, Judith (1997). 36:performative utterances 1420:Philosophy of language 1384:Philosophy of language 1021:Inalienable possession 1001:Free choice inferences 996:Faultless disagreement 767:Generalized quantifier 673:Sedgwick, Eve (2003). 607:. New York: Routledge. 327:Historical methodology 265:Postmodernist theories 198:How Performatives Work 132:"I name this ship the 117:performative sentences 28:philosophy of language 1279:Plural quantification 1173:Inquisitive semantics 1138:Alternative semantics 76:as another instance. 1264:Function application 1071:Responsive predicate 1061:Privative adjectives 389:performative writing 383:Performative writing 1349:Cognitive semantics 1314:Strawson entailment 1259:Existential closure 1203:Situation semantics 1106:Temperature paradox 1076:Rising declaratives 1041:Modal subordination 1016:Hurford disjunction 976:Discourse relations 647:Language in Society 631:Visions of Politics 422:Illocutionary force 80:Austin's definition 1394:Semantics of logic 1319:Strict conditional 1289:Quantifier raising 1254:Downward entailing 1234:Autonomy of syntax 1163:Generative grammar 1143:Categorial grammar 1081:Scalar implicature 986:Epistemic modality 961:De dicto and de re 344:The receiving side 109:illocutionary acts 32:speech acts theory 1402: 1401: 1374:Logic translation 1337: 1336: 1329:Universal grinder 1309:Squiggle operator 1269:Meaning postulate 1208:Supervaluationism 1178:Intensional logic 1158:Dynamic semantics 1119: 1118: 951:Crossover effects 900:Tense–aspect–mood 880:Lexical semantics 442:Performative turn 258:Richard Schechner 242:performative turn 223:Performative text 74:illocutionary act 55:argued against a 1432: 1379:Linguistics wars 1304:Semantic parsing 1193:Montague grammar 1128: 1127: 971:Deontic modality 825: 824: 812:Truth conditions 747:Compositionality 740:Central concepts 726: 719: 712: 703: 702: 679: 678: 675:Touching Feeling 670: 664: 663: 641: 635: 634: 626: 609: 608: 598: 585: 584: 576: 563: 562: 554: 548: 547: 539: 528: 527: 519: 508: 494: 472: 468: 393:critical writing 311:The philosopher 218: 1440: 1439: 1435: 1434: 1433: 1431: 1430: 1429: 1405: 1404: 1403: 1398: 1333: 1222: 1183:Lambda calculus 1115: 1086:Sloppy identity 1046:Opaque contexts 981:Donkey anaphora 946:Counterfactuals 914: 816: 735: 730: 697:Dinosaur Comics 688: 683: 682: 671: 667: 642: 638: 627: 612: 599: 588: 577: 566: 555: 551: 540: 531: 520: 511: 495: 486: 481: 476: 475: 469: 465: 460: 413: 401:performance art 385: 358: 346: 333:Quentin Skinner 329: 317:Michel Foucault 289:Jacques Derrida 282:Jacques Derrida 267: 246:social sciences 225: 212: 182: 134:Queen Elizabeth 102:truth-evaluable 100:, that is, not 82: 24: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1438: 1428: 1427: 1422: 1417: 1400: 1399: 1397: 1396: 1391: 1386: 1381: 1376: 1371: 1369:Inferentialism 1366: 1364:Formal grammar 1361: 1356: 1351: 1345: 1343: 1339: 1338: 1335: 1334: 1332: 1331: 1326: 1321: 1316: 1311: 1306: 1301: 1296: 1291: 1286: 1284:Possible world 1281: 1276: 1271: 1266: 1261: 1256: 1251: 1246: 1241: 1236: 1230: 1228: 1224: 1223: 1221: 1220: 1215: 1210: 1205: 1200: 1195: 1190: 1185: 1180: 1175: 1170: 1168:Glue semantics 1165: 1160: 1155: 1150: 1145: 1140: 1134: 1132: 1131:Formal systems 1125: 1121: 1120: 1117: 1116: 1114: 1113: 1108: 1103: 1098: 1093: 1088: 1083: 1078: 1073: 1068: 1063: 1058: 1056:Polarity items 1053: 1048: 1043: 1038: 1033: 1028: 1023: 1018: 1013: 1008: 1003: 998: 993: 988: 983: 978: 973: 968: 963: 958: 953: 948: 943: 941:Conservativity 938: 933: 928: 922: 920: 916: 915: 913: 912: 907: 905:Quantification 902: 897: 892: 887: 882: 877: 872: 867: 862: 857: 852: 847: 842: 837: 831: 829: 822: 818: 817: 815: 814: 809: 804: 799: 794: 789: 784: 782:Presupposition 779: 774: 769: 764: 759: 754: 749: 743: 741: 737: 736: 729: 728: 721: 714: 706: 700: 699: 694: 687: 686:External links 684: 681: 680: 665: 654:(2): 270–274. 636: 610: 586: 564: 549: 529: 509: 483: 482: 480: 477: 474: 473: 462: 461: 459: 456: 455: 454: 452:Performativity 449: 444: 439: 434: 429: 424: 419: 412: 409: 405:referentiality 384: 381: 357: 354: 345: 342: 331:The historian 328: 325: 266: 263: 224: 221: 181: 178: 144: 143: 140: 137: 130: 113: 112: 105: 81: 78: 66:interrogatives 21:Performativity 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1437: 1426: 1423: 1421: 1418: 1416: 1413: 1412: 1410: 1395: 1392: 1390: 1387: 1385: 1382: 1380: 1377: 1375: 1372: 1370: 1367: 1365: 1362: 1360: 1357: 1355: 1352: 1350: 1347: 1346: 1344: 1340: 1330: 1327: 1325: 1322: 1320: 1317: 1315: 1312: 1310: 1307: 1305: 1302: 1300: 1297: 1295: 1292: 1290: 1287: 1285: 1282: 1280: 1277: 1275: 1272: 1270: 1267: 1265: 1262: 1260: 1257: 1255: 1252: 1250: 1247: 1245: 1242: 1240: 1237: 1235: 1232: 1231: 1229: 1225: 1219: 1216: 1214: 1211: 1209: 1206: 1204: 1201: 1199: 1196: 1194: 1191: 1189: 1186: 1184: 1181: 1179: 1176: 1174: 1171: 1169: 1166: 1164: 1161: 1159: 1156: 1154: 1151: 1149: 1146: 1144: 1141: 1139: 1136: 1135: 1133: 1129: 1126: 1122: 1112: 1109: 1107: 1104: 1102: 1099: 1097: 1094: 1092: 1089: 1087: 1084: 1082: 1079: 1077: 1074: 1072: 1069: 1067: 1064: 1062: 1059: 1057: 1054: 1052: 1051:Performatives 1049: 1047: 1044: 1042: 1039: 1037: 1034: 1032: 1031:Logophoricity 1029: 1027: 1024: 1022: 1019: 1017: 1014: 1012: 1009: 1007: 1004: 1002: 999: 997: 994: 992: 989: 987: 984: 982: 979: 977: 974: 972: 969: 967: 964: 962: 959: 957: 954: 952: 949: 947: 944: 942: 939: 937: 934: 932: 929: 927: 924: 923: 921: 917: 911: 908: 906: 903: 901: 898: 896: 893: 891: 888: 886: 883: 881: 878: 876: 873: 871: 868: 866: 865:Evidentiality 863: 861: 858: 856: 853: 851: 848: 846: 843: 841: 838: 836: 833: 832: 830: 826: 823: 819: 813: 810: 808: 805: 803: 800: 798: 795: 793: 790: 788: 785: 783: 780: 778: 775: 773: 770: 768: 765: 763: 760: 758: 755: 753: 750: 748: 745: 744: 742: 738: 734: 727: 722: 720: 715: 713: 708: 707: 704: 698: 695: 693: 690: 689: 676: 669: 661: 657: 653: 649: 648: 640: 632: 625: 623: 621: 619: 617: 615: 606: 605: 597: 595: 593: 591: 582: 575: 573: 571: 569: 560: 553: 545: 538: 536: 534: 525: 518: 516: 514: 507: 506:0-19-824553-X 503: 499: 496:Austin, J.L. 493: 491: 489: 484: 467: 463: 453: 450: 448: 445: 443: 440: 438: 437:Judith Butler 435: 433: 430: 428: 425: 423: 420: 418: 415: 414: 408: 406: 402: 399:(often about 398: 394: 390: 380: 378: 374: 370: 366: 362: 353: 350: 341: 337: 334: 324: 320: 318: 314: 313:Judith Butler 309: 305: 301: 300:, to repeat. 299: 295: 290: 285: 283: 279: 274: 272: 271:postmodernism 262: 259: 253: 251: 247: 243: 239: 235: 230: 220: 216: 211: 207: 203: 199: 194: 190: 187: 177: 173: 171: 166: 164: 160: 156: 152: 151:performatives 150: 141: 138: 135: 131: 128: 127: 122: 121: 120: 118: 110: 106: 103: 99: 98:true or false 95: 94: 93: 91: 87: 77: 75: 71: 67: 63: 58: 54: 50: 49: 43: 41: 37: 33: 29: 22: 1324:Type shifter 1294:Quantization 1244:Continuation 1111:Veridicality 1050: 991:Exhaustivity 956:Cumulativity 875:Indexicality 855:Definiteness 850:Conditionals 777:Logical form 674: 668: 651: 645: 639: 630: 602: 580: 558: 552: 543: 523: 497: 466: 427:J. L. Austin 417:Eve Sedgwick 386: 377:gay marriage 361:Eve Sedgwick 359: 347: 338: 330: 321: 310: 306: 302: 297: 286: 275: 268: 254: 234:human agency 226: 205: 202:declarations 201: 197: 195: 191: 183: 174: 167: 162: 158: 148: 145: 133: 124: 116: 114: 89: 85: 83: 53:J. L. Austin 46: 44: 35: 25: 1239:Context set 1213:Type theory 1096:Subtrigging 860:Disjunction 787:Proposition 581:Limited Inc 432:John Searle 397:performance 213: [ 206:declaration 186:John Searle 180:John Searle 64:sentences, 62:nonsensical 1415:Pragmatics 1409:Categories 1389:Pragmatics 1036:Mirativity 802:Speech act 757:Entailment 752:Denotation 479:References 447:Pragmatics 294:speech act 278:postmodern 250:humanities 210:assertives 70:directives 57:positivist 1188:Mereology 1124:Formalism 1006:Givenness 931:Cataphora 919:Phenomena 910:Vagueness 840:Ambiguity 792:Reference 772:Intension 762:Extension 369:sentences 349:Kent Bach 238:discourse 40:sentences 1342:See also 1227:Concepts 1101:Telicity 936:Coercion 890:Negation 885:Modality 835:Anaphora 411:See also 280:thinker 163:explicit 149:explicit 845:Binding 660:4167219 583:: 1–23. 373:phrases 298:iterare 244:in the 123:"I do ( 26:In the 1274:Monads 821:Topics 658:  504:  395:about 371:, and 966:De se 870:Focus 828:Areas 797:Scope 656:JSTOR 458:Notes 365:words 217:] 502:ISBN 248:and 236:and 229:text 38:are 30:and 1218:TTR 161:an 159:not 126:sc. 90:are 86:are 1411:: 652:10 650:. 613:^ 589:^ 567:^ 532:^ 512:^ 487:^ 367:, 284:. 219:. 215:de 68:, 51:, 34:, 725:e 718:t 711:v 662:. 136:" 23:.

Index

Performativity
philosophy of language
speech acts theory
sentences
How to Do Things with Words
J. L. Austin
positivist
nonsensical
interrogatives
directives
illocutionary act
true or false
truth-evaluable
illocutionary acts
sc.
explicit performatives
"inexplicit" performatives
"I divorce you", said three times by a man to his wife
John Searle
assertives
de
text
human agency
discourse
performative turn
social sciences
humanities
Richard Schechner
postmodernism
postmodern

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑