Knowledge

Direct and indirect realism

Source đź“ť

398:
process of hallucination. However, if there are visual images when we hallucinate it seems reasonable that there are visual images when we see. Similarly if dreaming involves visual and auditory images in our minds it seems reasonable to think there are visual and auditory images, or sense-data, when we are awake and perceiving things. This argument has been challenged in a number of different ways. First it has been questioned whether there must be some object present that actually has the experienced qualities, which would then seemingly have to be something like a sense-datum. Why couldn't it be that the perceiver is simply in a state of seeming to experience such an object without any object actually being present? Second, in cases of illusion and perceptual relativity there is an object present which is simply misperceived, usually in readily explainable ways, and no need to suppose that an additional object is also involved. Third, the last part of the perceptual relativity version of the argument has been challenged by questioning whether there is really no experiential difference between veridical and non-veridical perception; and by arguing that even if sense-data are experienced in non-veridical cases and even if the difference between veridical and non-veridical cases is, as claimed, experientially indiscernible, there is still no reason to think that sense-data are the immediate objects of experience in veridical cases. Fourth, do sense-data exist through time or are they momentary? Can they exist when not being perceived? Are they public or private? Can they be themselves misperceived? Do they exist in minds or are they extra-mental, even if not physical? On the basis of the intractability of these questions, it has been argued that the conclusion of the argument from illusion is unacceptable or even unintelligible, even in the absence of a clear diagnosis of exactly where and how it goes wrong.
385:, the object has qualities that no public physical object in that situation has and so must be distinct from any such object. NaĂŻve realism may accommodate these facts as they stand by virtue of its very vagueness (or "open-texture"): it is not specific or detailed enough to be refuted by such cases. A more developed direct realist might respond by showing that various cases of misperception, failed perception, and perceptual relativity do not make it necessary to suppose that sense-data exist. When a stick submerged in water looks bent a direct realist is not compelled to say the stick actually is bent but can say that the stick can have more than one appearance: a straight stick can look bent when light reflected from the stick arrives at one's eye in a crooked pattern, but this appearance is not necessarily a sense-datum in the mind. Similar things can be said about the coin which appears circular from one vantage point and oval-shaped from another. Pressing on your eyeball with a finger creates double vision but assuming the existence of two sense-data is unnecessary: the direct realist can say that they have two eyes, each giving them a different view of the world. Usually the eyes are focused in the same direction; but sometimes they are not. 492:
to the input. This implies that the colour we experience is actually a cortical occurrence, and that light rays and external surfaces are not themselves coloured. The proportional variations with which cortical colour changes are there in the external world, but not colour as we experience it. Contrary to what Gilbert Ryle believed, those who argue for sensations being brain processes do not have to hold that there is a "picture" in the brain since this is impossible according to this theory since actual pictures in the external world are not coloured. It is plain that Ryle unthinkingly carried over what the eyes do to the nature of sensation; A. J. Ayer at the time described Ryle's position as "very weak". So there is no "screen" in front of cortical "eyes", no mental objects before one. As
402:
view, similar to Reid's, is that we do have images of various sorts in our minds when we perceive, dream, hallucinate and imagine but when we actually perceive things, our sensations cannot be considered objects of perception or attention. The only objects of perception are external objects. Even if perception is accompanied by images, or sensations, it is wrong to say we perceive sensations. Direct realism defines perception as perception of external objects where an "external object" is allowed to be a photon in the eye but not an impulse in a nerve leading from the eye. Recent work in neuroscience suggests a shared ontology for perception, imagination and dreaming, with similar areas of brain being used for all of these.
501:
an informative statement begins with the parties hypothetically assuming that they are referring to the "same" entity or "property", even though their selections from their sensory fields cannot match; we can call this mutually imagined projection the "logical subject" of the statement. The speaker then produces the logical predicate which effects the proposed updating of the "referent". If the statement goes through, the hearer will now have a different percept and concept of the "referent"—perhaps even seeing it now as two things and not one. The radical conclusion is that we are premature in conceiving of the external as already sorted into singular "objects" in the first place, since we only need to behave
410:
process may have been like. Furthermore, the causal process that intervenes between the external object and the perceptual experience takes time, so that the character of the experience reflects, at the most, an earlier stage of that object than the one existing at the moment of perception. As in observations of astronomical objects the external object may have ceased to exist long before the experience occurs. These facts are claimed to point to the conclusion that the direct object of experience is an entity produced at the end of this causal process, distinct from any physical object that initiates the process."
770:
the form of the material object without the matter. What we perceive directly, on this view, are material objects. This changed in the seventeenth century with Descartes and Locke. who can be read as saying that the primary objects of perception are not things external to the mind but sense-data. Sense-data are the messengers that stand between us and physical objects such as tables and chairs. While indirect realism was the standard view of early modern philosophers, nowadays direct realism is, once again, in fashion.
394:
out of any such set of related perceptual experiences as the one in which the relevant physical object is itself immediately experienced. The most reasonable conclusion is that the experienced object is always distinct from the physical object or at least that there is no way to identify which, if any, of the immediately experienced objects is the physical object itself. Epistemologically it is as though physical objects were never given, whether or not that is in fact the case.
366: 553:(the sense-datum) which that act apprehends or is an awareness of. The fundamental idea of the adverbial theory, in contrast, is that there is no need for such objects and the problems that they bring with them (such as whether they are physical or mental or somehow neither). Instead, it is suggested, merely the occurrence of a mental act or mental state with its own intrinsic character is enough to account for the character of immediate experience. 323: 447:). Although Descartes' duality of natural substances may have echoes in modern physics (Bose and Fermi statistics) no agreed account of 'interpretation' has been formulated. Thus representationalism remains an incomplete description of perception. Aristotle realized this and simply proposed that ideas themselves (representations) must be aware—in other words that there is no further transfer of sense impressions beyond ideas. 451: 38: 471:
representation. However, this is a distortion of the meaning of the word "see" which the representationalist does not imply. For the representationalist the statement refers to the Eiffel Tower, which implicitly is experienced in the form of a representation. The representationalist does not imply that when a person refers to the Eiffel Tower, they are referring to their
186:
example, one perceives an object as spherical precisely because of the way the atoms of the sphere are arranged.) Primary qualities cannot be removed by either thought or physical action, and include mass, movement, and, controversially, solidity (although later proponents of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities usually discount solidity).
346:). It has been argued that "informed commonsense" indicates that perceptions often depend on organs of perception. For example, humans would receive visual information very differently if they, like flies, had compound eyes, and may not even be able to imagine how things would appear with entirely different sense organs such as 562:
shape because an object or entity that literally has that color and shape is directly before my mind. But the nature of these entities and the way in which they are related to the mind are difficult to understand. The adverbial theory has the advantage of being metaphysically simpler, avoiding issues
558:
specific manner of sensing or of being appeared to accounts for the content of my experience: I am in a certain distinctive sort of experiential state. There need be no object or entity of any sort that is literally silver and elliptical in the material world or in the mind. I experience a silver and
409:
processes, without change in the external physical object that initiates this process and that may seem to be depicted by the experience. Conversely any process that yields the same sensory/neural results will yield the same perceptual experience, no matter what the physical object that initiated the
514:
that 'it' is singular. A proponent of this theory can thus ask the direct realist why he or she thinks it is necessary to move to taking the imagining of singularity for real when there is no practical difference in the outcome in action. Therefore, although there are selections from our sensory
500:
A more fundamental criticism is implied in theories of this type. The differences at the sensory and perceptual levels between agents require that some means of ensuring at least a partial correlation can be achieved that allows the updatings involved in communication to take place. The process in
491:
with what arrives at the retinas. Just as the currents in a wire going to a loudspeaker vary proportionately with the sounds that emanate from it but have no other likeness, so too does sensation vary proportionately (and not necessarily directly) with what causes it but bears no other resemblance
486:
The new objection to the Homunculus Argument claims that it relies on a naive view of sensation. Because the eyes respond to light rays, there is no reason for supposing that the visual field requires eyes to see it. Visual sensation (the argument can be extrapolated to the other senses) bears no
478:
Furthermore, representative realism claims that we perceive our perceptual intermediaries—we can attend to them—just as we observe our image in a mirror. However, as we can scientifically verify, this is clearly not true of the physiological components of the perceptual process. This also brings up
393:
is based upon observation then the entire developed memory and knowledge of every perception and of each sense may be as skewed as the bent stick. Since objects with different qualities are experienced from each of the different perspectives there is no apparent experiential basis for regarding one
769:
The distinction between direct and indirect realism about perception has an interesting history. There was a time when perception was understood to be of things themselves, not of our ideas of things. This is what we find in Aristotle and Aquinas, who maintain that the mind or understanding grasps
388:
However, this response is presumably based on previously observed data. If one were to be able to observe nothing other than the stick in the water, with no previous information, it would appear that the stick was bent. Visual depth in particular is a set of inferences, not an actual experience of
189:
Secondary qualities are qualities that one's experience does not directly resemble; for example, when one sees an object as red, the sensation of seeing redness is not produced by some quality of redness in the object, but by the arrangement of atoms on the surface of the object which reflects and
519:
of pre-existing singularities, they retain an experimental character. Virtual constructs or no, they remain, however, selections that are causally linked to the real and can surprise us at any time—which removes any danger of solipsism in this theory. This approach dovetails with the philosophy
401:
Direct realists can potentially deny the existence of any such thing as a mental image but this is difficult to maintain, since we seem able to visually imagine all sorts of things with ease. Even if perception does not involve images other mental processes like imagination certainly seem to. One
110:
Conversely, direct realism postulates that conscious subjects view the world directly, treating concepts as a 1:1 correspondence. Furthermore, the framework rejects the premise that knowledge arrives via a representational medium, as well as the notion that concepts are interpretations of sensory
397:
Another potential counter-example involves vivid hallucinations: phantom elephants, for instance, might be interpreted as sense-data. A direct realist response would differentiate hallucination from genuine perception: no perception of elephants is going on, only the different and related mental
185:
Primary qualities are qualities which are "explanatorily basic" – which is to say, they can be referred to as the explanation for other qualities or phenomena without requiring explanation themselves – and they are distinct in that our sensory experience of them resembles them in reality. (For
557:
According to the adverbial theory, when, for example, I experience a silver elliptical shape (as when viewing a coin from an angle) I am in a certain specific state of sensing or sensory awareness or of being appeared to: I sense in a certain manner or am appeared to in a certain way, and that
458:
A potential difficulty with representational realism is that, if we only have knowledge of representations of the world, how can we know that they resemble in any significant way the objects to which they are supposed to correspond? Any creature with a representation in its brain would need to
459:
interact with the objects that are represented to identify them with the representation. This difficulty would seem reasonably to be covered by the learning by exploration of the world that goes on throughout life. However, there may still be a concern that if the external world is only to be
470:
in representationalism. If a person says "I see the Eiffel Tower" at a time when they are indeed looking at the Eiffel Tower, to what does the term "Eiffel Tower" refer? The direct realist might say that in the representational account people do not really see the tower but rather 'see' the
496:
put it: "How do we take notice of sense?—by sense itself". Moreland Perkins has characterized it thus: that sensing is not like kicking a ball, but rather "kicking a kick". Today there are still philosophers arguing for colour being a property of external surfaces, light sources, etc.
505:
they are already logically singular. The diagram at the beginning of this entry would thus be thought of as a false picture of the actual case, since to draw "an" object as already selected from the real is only to treat the practically needful, but strictly false, hypothesis of
463:, its 'true likeness' might be quite different from our idea of it. The representational realist would answer to this that "true likeness" is an intuitive concept that falls in the face of logic, since a likeness must always depend on the way in which something is considered. 309:", one particular to ourselves in its detail. The question has to be put how a collective use of language can go on when, not only do we have differing understandings of the words we use, but our sensory registrations differ. 487:
direct resemblance to the light rays at the retina, nor to the character of what they are reflected from or pass through or what was glowing at the origin of them. The reason given is that they only bear the similarities of
434:
philosophers prior to Newton, such as Descartes, for whom physical processes were poorly defined. Descartes held that there is a "homunculus" in the form of the soul, belonging to a form of natural substance known as
532:
The above argument invites the conclusion of a perceptual dualism that raises the issue of how and whether the object can be known by experience. The adverbial theory proposes "that this dualism is a dualism of
430:, and this need not be implied. This suggests that some phenomenon other than simple data flow and information processing is involved in perception. This is more of an issue now than it was for 326:
Illusion creates a problem for naĂŻve realists as it suggests our senses are fallible, perceiving things that are not there. In this illusion, the lines are horizontal, despite how they appear.
895:, Hackett Publishing, 2003, p. xviii: "Hegel follows Kant ... in limiting claims to know to the empirically real. In short, he adopts a view very similar to Kant's empirical realism." 289:. Recently, reliance on the private language argument and the "homunculus objection" has itself come under attack. It can be argued that those who argue for "inner presence", to use 563:
about the nature of sense-data, but we gain no real understanding of the nature of the states in question or of how exactly they account for the character of immediate experience."
91:
that subjects do not experience the external world as it really is, but perceive it through the lens of a conceptual framework. Furthermore, indirect realism is a core tenet of the
823:: "Paraphrasing David Hume (1739...; see also Locke 1690, Berkeley 1710, Russell 1912): nothing is ever directly present to the mind in perception except perceptual appearances." 405:
The character of experience of a physical object can be altered in major ways by changes in the conditions of perception or of the relevant sense-organs and the resulting
1123: 1309:
Harold I. Brown, "Direct Realism, Indirect Realism, and Epistemology". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 52, No. 2. (Jun., 1992), pp. 341–363.
515:
fields which for the time being we treat as if they were objects, they are only provisional, open to corrections at any time, and, hence, far from being direct
362:. More dramatically, sometimes people perceive things which are not there at all, which can be termed instances of "hallucination" or "perceptual delusion". 301:
language. There is no doubt that each of us has a private understanding of public language, a notion that has been experimentally supported;
1974: 80:
question of whether the world we see around us is the real world itself or merely an internal perceptual copy of that world generated by our
1150: 645: 578: 335: 757: 373:
are an example of a perceptual delusion. "For, unlike an architectural arch, a rainbow recedes as we approach it, never to be reached."
1338: 947:
Putnam, Hilary. Sep. 1994. "The Dewey Lectures 1994: Sense, Nonsense, and the Senses: An Inquiry into the Powers of the Human Mind."
816: 699: 293:'s term, are not proposing a private "referent", with the application of language to it being "private" and thus unshareable, but a 1099: 669: 1369: 1312: 2025: 1984: 354:
devices. Furthermore, perception systems can misrepresent objects even when in full working order, as shown, for example, by
178: 1176: 506:
objects-as-logically-singular as ontologically given. The proponents of this view thus argue that there is no need actually
419: 281:
in his seminal essay "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind". Indirect realism is argued to be problematical because of
1793: 1120: 483:
and its relation to representative realism, concerning the incongruous marriage of the metaphysical and the physical.
2015: 2010: 1764: 1641: 1294: 743: 919:
Bertrand Russell and the Nature of Propositions: A History and Defence of the Multiple Relation Theory of Judgement
17: 422:
is assumed then something in the brain must be interpreting incoming data. This something is often described as a
1320: 1904: 2020: 381:
allegedly shows the need to posit sense-data as the immediate objects of perception. In cases of illusion or
269:
However, epistemological dualism has come under sustained attack by other contemporary philosophers, such as
198: 1843: 1195:
Sellars, Roy Wood (1919), "The epistemology of evolutionary naturalism", Mind, 28:112, 407-26; se p. 414.
1838: 1654: 997: 2005: 1362: 607: 601: 1303: 1979: 1780: 1772: 1669: 1514: 1251:
66: 173-78; Matthen, Mohan (2009), 'Truly blue: an adverbial aspect of perceptual representation',
274: 1306:- A short article, aimed at the general public, arguing for the representative theory of perception. 1941: 1853: 1749: 1714: 1474: 1334:
McCreery, C. (2006) "Perception and Hallucination: the Case for Continuity.” Oxford: Oxford Forum.
707: 92: 46: 2030: 1921: 1754: 1630: 1564: 1386: 1147: 619: 239: 155: 359: 190:
absorbs light in a particular way. Secondary qualities include colour, smell, sound, and taste.
1868: 1788: 642: 378: 232: 208: 1969: 1946: 1926: 1808: 1679: 1619: 1355: 1131: 733: 595: 521: 475:, and when another person refers to the Tower, they are referring to their sense experience. 31: 1329: 537:, with perceptual experience being a more direct experience of objects of a different sort, 1878: 1863: 1335: 1494: 813: 389:
the space between things in a radial direction outward from the observation point. If all
8: 1956: 1951: 1931: 1833: 1818: 1813: 1614: 1096: 286: 270: 140: 426:, although the term homunculus is also used to imply an entity that creates a continual 1609: 1399: 643:
The Function of Conscious Experience: An Analogical Paradigm of Perception and Behavior
472: 390: 50: 666: 1858: 1039: 749: 739: 480: 351: 282: 224: 103:. While there is superficial overlap, the indirect model is unlike the standpoint of 100: 1439: 581: â€“ Theory that some of our sense-data can accurately represent external objects 159: 1936: 1888: 1823: 1574: 1549: 1509: 1424: 437: 427: 355: 247: 220: 129: 107:, which holds that only ideas are real, but there are no mind-independent objects. 41:
Direct realism, also known as naĂŻve realism, argues we perceive the world directly.
1709: 1828: 1694: 1689: 1584: 1539: 1419: 1342: 1324: 1180: 1173: 1154: 1143: 1127: 1103: 1001: 820: 673: 649: 406: 331: 278: 219:
followed Kant in adopting empirical realism. Direct realism was also defended by
136:
carried over the intervening material continuum with which the eye is impressed.
201:
was a proponent of direct realism. Direct realist views have been attributed to
1604: 1599: 1589: 1499: 1464: 1454: 1429: 1404: 1394: 1298: 1044:
On Message Structure: A Framework for the Study of Language and Communication,
339: 302: 290: 263: 259: 243: 216: 202: 148: 144: 1999: 1719: 1659: 1624: 1559: 1534: 1529: 1489: 1459: 584: 493: 382: 255: 251: 228: 167: 81: 70: 1803: 1734: 1579: 1449: 1434: 1378: 888: 872: 613: 338:)." It is also referred to as the problem of conflicting appearances (e.g. 212: 133: 77: 689:
Schacter, Daniel (2011). Psychology. Worth Publishers. ISBN 9781429237192.
610: â€“ Relationship between an object and a representation of that object 330:
This argument was "first offered in a more or less fully explicit form in
1883: 1739: 1729: 1674: 1649: 1594: 1569: 1554: 1524: 1504: 1479: 1409: 1317: 700:"Epistemological Problems of Perception - 2.2 Idealism and Phenomenalism" 443: 431: 365: 194: 124: 1893: 1873: 1724: 1699: 1664: 1519: 1484: 1469: 1444: 1414: 589: 538: 423: 171: 163: 96: 88: 1336:
An analysis of empirical arguments for representationalism. Online PDF
976:
Roger F. Gibson, "McDowell's Direct Realism and Platonic Naturalism",
510:
in the singularity of an object since we can manage perfectly well by
1848: 572: 467: 460: 347: 119: 893:
Before and After Hegel: A Historical Introduction to Hegel's Thought
1704: 370: 306: 104: 753: 418:
One concern with indirect realism is that if simple data flow and
1684: 559: 450: 322: 87:
Indirect realism is broadly equivalent to the scientific view of
37: 1798: 1347: 814:
The Problem of Perception (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
73: 441:
that obeyed different laws from those obeyed by solid matter (
1898: 1544: 994: 616: â€“ Philosophy that accords primacy only to human thought 122:
was the first to provide a description of direct realism. In
1004:, a lecture recorded 2014 at Marc Sanders Foundation, Vimeo. 1232:
Elements of Philosophy, The First Section: Concerning Body,
1028:
Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon,
1313:
What Do We Perceive and How Do We Perceive It? (PDF file)
906:
The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy
1279:
Radical Constructivism: A Way of Knowing and Learning,
1234:
London: John Bohn, p. 389; Perkins, Moreland (1983),
738:. Philosophical Studies Series. Springer. p. 62. 413: 1318:
Neurological explanation for paranormal experiences
832:A. D. Smith, "On Primary and Secondary Qualities", 312: 69:, are differing models that describe the nature of 1057:After Babel: Aspects of Language and Translation, 1174:The Empirical Description of Conscious Experience 1015:Seeing Things as They Are: A Theory of Perception 466:A semantic difficulty may arise when considering 1997: 1059:London & New York: Oxford University Press. 1247:Michael Tye (2006), 'The puzzle of true blue', 727: 725: 1268:Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 103-120. 877:Fichte, German Idealism, and Early Romanticism 305:refers to our personal use of language as an " 1363: 1238:Indianapolis IN: Hackett Pub. Co., pp. 286-7. 1208:Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 96-102. 786:Realism and Appearances: An Essay in Ontology 128:he describes how a see-er is informed of the 1185:The Science and Philosophy of Consciousness. 932:Husserl's Position in the School of Brentano 722: 1266:Narrative, Perception, Language, and Faith, 1206:Narrative, Perception, Language, and Faith, 788:, Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 136. 1370: 1356: 938:150, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999, p. 224 n. 1. 801:, Cambridge University Press, 2003, p. 85. 598:, also known as Hallucinations in the sane 154:Indirect realism was popular with several 111:input derived from a real external world. 731: 575: â€“ Art depicting Outward Appearances 454:The representational theory of perception 317: 227:lectures (1889–1915). On the other hand, 30:For representationalism in the arts, see 967:. Harvard University Press, 1994, p. 26. 862:, Oxford University Press, 2017, p. 288. 809: 807: 780: 778: 667:NaĂŻve Realism in Contemporary Philosophy 449: 364: 321: 242:, indirect realism has been defended by 36: 1017:, Oxford University Press, 2015, p. 15. 908:, Oxford University Press, 2013, p. 40. 14: 1998: 1116: 1114: 1112: 1106:, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 1097:Epistemological Problems of Perception 1092: 1090: 1088: 1086: 1084: 1082: 1080: 1078: 799:Kant on Representation and Objectivity 624: â€“ 1929 painting by RenĂ© Magritte 549:of awareness (or apprehension) and an 250:. Direct realism has been defended by 1351: 804: 775: 1295:Online papers on representationalism 678:The Function of Conscious Experience 635: 1109: 1075: 704:Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 527: 235:") subscribed to indirect realism. 24: 1297:, by various authors, compiled by 1072:Indianapolis IN: Hackett Pub. Co. 414:Arguments against indirect realism 25: 2042: 1288: 659: 369:Illusions are present in nature. 1377: 1330:The Representationalism Web Site 313:Arguments against direct realism 27:Debate in the philosophy of mind 1277:Glasersfeld, Ernst von (1995), 1271: 1258: 1241: 1224: 1211: 1198: 1189: 1166: 1137: 1062: 1049: 1046:London: John Wiley & Sons. 1033: 1020: 1007: 987: 970: 957: 941: 924: 911: 898: 882: 865: 852: 839: 760:from the original on 2019-12-20 1794:Analytic–synthetic distinction 1221:Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. 860:The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza 826: 791: 692: 683: 604:, also known as Inferentialism 541:." Perceptual dualism implies: 13: 1: 706:. Dec 5, 2016. Archived from 628: 592: â€“ Philosophical concept 199:Scottish common sense realism 2026:Dualism (philosophy of mind) 7: 1839:Internalism and externalism 858:Michael Della Rocca (ed.), 654:Consciousness and Cognition 566: 10: 2047: 602:Inferential role semantics 197:, a notable member of the 114: 29: 1965: 1914: 1763: 1670:Evolutionary epistemology 1640: 1385: 1281:London: RoutledgeFalmer. 1219:The Problem of Knowledge, 1030:Cambridge MA: MIT Press. 949:The Journal of Philosophy 921:, Routledge, 2017, p. 34. 849:, Routledge, 2017, p. 18. 847:New Essays on Thomas Reid 735:The Metaphysics of Memory 275:private language argument 156:early modern philosophers 2016:Epistemological theories 2011:Philosophy of perception 1942:Philosophy of perception 1745:Representational realism 1715:Naturalized epistemology 1230:Hobbes, Thomas (1839 ), 1055:Steiner, George (1998), 209:Late modern philosophers 67:representational realism 47:philosophy of perception 1922:Outline of epistemology 1755:Transcendental idealism 1264:Wright, Edmond (2005), 1204:Wright, Edmond (2005), 1070:Color for Philosophers, 1026:Revonsuo, Antti (2006) 621:The Treachery of Images 344:Conflicting Appearances 240:contemporary philosophy 233:Ăśber Sinn und Bedeutung 1869:Problem of other minds 904:Michael Beaney (ed.), 879:, Rodopi, 2010, p. 20. 732:Bernecker, S. (2008). 665:Lehar, Steve. (2000). 641:Lehar, Steve. (2000). 608:Map–territory relation 555: 455: 420:information processing 379:argument from illusion 374: 327: 318:Argument from illusion 42: 1947:Philosophy of science 1927:Faith and rationality 1809:Descriptive knowledge 1680:Feminist epistemology 1620:Nicholas Wolterstorff 1172:Green, Alex. (2003). 1132:University of Reading 1068:Hardin, C. L. (1988) 995:"Real Direct Realism" 871:Daniel Breazeale and 596:Anomalous experiences 543: 522:social constructivism 453: 368: 325: 40: 32:Realism (visual arts) 2021:Metaphysical realism 1879:Procedural knowledge 1864:Problem of induction 1304:This is a simulation 984:(1996), pp. 275–281. 978:Philosophical Issues 930:Robin D. Rollinger, 834:Philosophical Review 360:MĂĽller-Lyer illusion 231:(in his 1892 paper " 1957:Virtue epistemology 1952:Social epistemology 1932:Formal epistemology 1819:Epistemic injustice 1814:Exploratory thought 1615:Ludwig Wittgenstein 1217:Ayer, A. J. (1957) 287:homunculus argument 271:Ludwig Wittgenstein 141:medieval philosophy 1610:Timothy Williamson 1400:Augustine of Hippo 1341:2019-12-10 at the 1323:2008-05-27 at the 1236:Sensing the World, 1179:2011-08-05 at the 1153:2011-07-15 at the 1126:2009-10-02 at the 1102:2011-05-25 at the 1040:Rommetveit, Ragnar 1000:2017-01-16 at the 819:2019-12-09 at the 672:2012-08-11 at the 648:2019-06-03 at the 512:mutually imagining 456: 407:neurophysiological 391:empirical evidence 375: 328: 177:Locke categorized 51:philosophy of mind 43: 2006:Cognitive science 1993: 1992: 1859:Privileged access 1495:Søren Kierkegaard 1144:Gregory, Richard. 797:A. B. Dickerson, 356:optical illusions 101:cognitive science 16:(Redirected from 2038: 1937:Metaepistemology 1915:Related articles 1889:Regress argument 1824:Epistemic virtue 1575:Bertrand Russell 1550:Duncan Pritchard 1510:Hilary Kornblith 1425:Laurence BonJour 1372: 1365: 1358: 1349: 1348: 1282: 1275: 1269: 1262: 1256: 1245: 1239: 1228: 1222: 1215: 1209: 1202: 1196: 1193: 1187: 1170: 1164: 1141: 1135: 1118: 1107: 1094: 1073: 1066: 1060: 1053: 1047: 1037: 1031: 1024: 1018: 1013:John R. Searle, 1011: 1005: 993:Galen Strawson, 991: 985: 974: 968: 961: 955: 945: 939: 936:Phaenomenologica 928: 922: 915: 909: 902: 896: 886: 880: 869: 863: 856: 850: 845:Patrick Rysiew, 843: 837: 830: 824: 811: 802: 795: 789: 784:John W. Yolton, 782: 773: 772: 766: 765: 729: 720: 719: 717: 715: 696: 690: 687: 681: 663: 657: 639: 579:Critical realism 528:Adverbial theory 473:sense experience 248:Bertrand Russell 221:John Cook Wilson 147:was defended by 134:hylomorphic form 61:, as opposed to 21: 18:Indirect realism 2046: 2045: 2041: 2040: 2039: 2037: 2036: 2035: 1996: 1995: 1994: 1989: 1961: 1910: 1829:Gettier problem 1759: 1690:Foundationalism 1636: 1585:Wilfrid Sellars 1540:Alvin Plantinga 1420:George Berkeley 1387:Epistemologists 1381: 1376: 1343:Wayback Machine 1325:Wayback Machine 1291: 1286: 1285: 1276: 1272: 1263: 1259: 1246: 1242: 1229: 1225: 1216: 1212: 1203: 1199: 1194: 1190: 1181:Wayback Machine 1171: 1167: 1155:Wayback Machine 1142: 1138: 1128:Wayback Machine 1119: 1110: 1104:Wayback Machine 1095: 1076: 1067: 1063: 1054: 1050: 1038: 1034: 1025: 1021: 1012: 1008: 1002:Wayback Machine 992: 988: 975: 971: 963:John McDowell, 962: 958: 946: 942: 929: 925: 917:Samuel Lebens, 916: 912: 903: 899: 887: 883: 870: 866: 857: 853: 844: 840: 836:(1990), 221–54. 831: 827: 821:Wayback Machine 812: 805: 796: 792: 783: 776: 763: 761: 746: 730: 723: 713: 711: 710:on Apr 26, 2022 698: 697: 693: 688: 684: 674:Wayback Machine 664: 660: 650:Wayback Machine 640: 636: 631: 569: 530: 517:representations 479:the problem of 416: 320: 315: 279:Wilfrid Sellars 117: 35: 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 2044: 2034: 2033: 2031:Theory of mind 2028: 2023: 2018: 2013: 2008: 1991: 1990: 1988: 1987: 1982: 1977: 1972: 1966: 1963: 1962: 1960: 1959: 1954: 1949: 1944: 1939: 1934: 1929: 1924: 1918: 1916: 1912: 1911: 1909: 1908: 1901: 1896: 1891: 1886: 1881: 1876: 1871: 1866: 1861: 1856: 1851: 1846: 1841: 1836: 1831: 1826: 1821: 1816: 1811: 1806: 1801: 1796: 1791: 1786: 1778: 1769: 1767: 1761: 1760: 1758: 1757: 1752: 1747: 1742: 1737: 1732: 1727: 1722: 1717: 1712: 1707: 1702: 1697: 1692: 1687: 1682: 1677: 1672: 1667: 1662: 1657: 1655:Constructivism 1652: 1646: 1644: 1638: 1637: 1635: 1634: 1627: 1622: 1617: 1612: 1607: 1605:Baruch Spinoza 1602: 1600:P. F. Strawson 1597: 1592: 1590:Susanna Siegel 1587: 1582: 1577: 1572: 1567: 1565:W. V. O. Quine 1562: 1557: 1552: 1547: 1542: 1537: 1532: 1527: 1522: 1517: 1512: 1507: 1502: 1497: 1492: 1487: 1482: 1477: 1472: 1467: 1465:Nelson Goodman 1462: 1457: 1455:Edmund Gettier 1452: 1447: 1442: 1440:RenĂ© Descartes 1437: 1432: 1430:Gilles Deleuze 1427: 1422: 1417: 1412: 1407: 1405:William Alston 1402: 1397: 1395:Thomas Aquinas 1391: 1389: 1383: 1382: 1375: 1374: 1367: 1360: 1352: 1346: 1345: 1332: 1327: 1315: 1310: 1307: 1301: 1299:David Chalmers 1290: 1289:External links 1287: 1284: 1283: 1270: 1257: 1240: 1223: 1210: 1197: 1188: 1165: 1163:, pp. 257-261. 1136: 1108: 1074: 1061: 1048: 1032: 1019: 1006: 986: 969: 965:Mind and World 956: 940: 923: 910: 897: 881: 864: 851: 838: 825: 803: 790: 774: 744: 721: 691: 682: 658: 633: 632: 630: 627: 626: 625: 617: 611: 605: 599: 593: 587: 582: 576: 568: 565: 529: 526: 415: 412: 340:Myles Burnyeat 319: 316: 314: 311: 303:George Steiner 291:Antti Revonsuo 283:Ryle's regress 264:John R. Searle 260:Galen Strawson 244:Edmund Husserl 217:G. W. F. Hegel 203:Baruch Spinoza 192: 191: 187: 160:RenĂ© Descartes 149:Thomas Aquinas 145:direct realism 132:by way of the 116: 113: 26: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 2043: 2032: 2029: 2027: 2024: 2022: 2019: 2017: 2014: 2012: 2009: 2007: 2004: 2003: 2001: 1986: 1983: 1981: 1978: 1976: 1973: 1971: 1968: 1967: 1964: 1958: 1955: 1953: 1950: 1948: 1945: 1943: 1940: 1938: 1935: 1933: 1930: 1928: 1925: 1923: 1920: 1919: 1917: 1913: 1907: 1906: 1902: 1900: 1897: 1895: 1892: 1890: 1887: 1885: 1882: 1880: 1877: 1875: 1872: 1870: 1867: 1865: 1862: 1860: 1857: 1855: 1852: 1850: 1847: 1845: 1844:Justification 1842: 1840: 1837: 1835: 1832: 1830: 1827: 1825: 1822: 1820: 1817: 1815: 1812: 1810: 1807: 1805: 1802: 1800: 1797: 1795: 1792: 1790: 1787: 1785: 1783: 1779: 1777: 1775: 1771: 1770: 1768: 1766: 1762: 1756: 1753: 1751: 1748: 1746: 1743: 1741: 1738: 1736: 1733: 1731: 1728: 1726: 1723: 1721: 1720:Phenomenalism 1718: 1716: 1713: 1711: 1710:NaĂŻve realism 1708: 1706: 1703: 1701: 1698: 1696: 1693: 1691: 1688: 1686: 1683: 1681: 1678: 1676: 1673: 1671: 1668: 1666: 1663: 1661: 1660:Contextualism 1658: 1656: 1653: 1651: 1648: 1647: 1645: 1643: 1639: 1633: 1632: 1628: 1626: 1625:Vienna Circle 1623: 1621: 1618: 1616: 1613: 1611: 1608: 1606: 1603: 1601: 1598: 1596: 1593: 1591: 1588: 1586: 1583: 1581: 1578: 1576: 1573: 1571: 1568: 1566: 1563: 1561: 1560:Hilary Putnam 1558: 1556: 1553: 1551: 1548: 1546: 1543: 1541: 1538: 1536: 1535:Robert Nozick 1533: 1531: 1530:John McDowell 1528: 1526: 1523: 1521: 1518: 1516: 1513: 1511: 1508: 1506: 1503: 1501: 1498: 1496: 1493: 1491: 1490:Immanuel Kant 1488: 1486: 1483: 1481: 1478: 1476: 1473: 1471: 1468: 1466: 1463: 1461: 1460:Alvin Goldman 1458: 1456: 1453: 1451: 1448: 1446: 1443: 1441: 1438: 1436: 1433: 1431: 1428: 1426: 1423: 1421: 1418: 1416: 1413: 1411: 1408: 1406: 1403: 1401: 1398: 1396: 1393: 1392: 1390: 1388: 1384: 1380: 1373: 1368: 1366: 1361: 1359: 1354: 1353: 1350: 1344: 1340: 1337: 1333: 1331: 1328: 1326: 1322: 1319: 1316: 1314: 1311: 1308: 1305: 1302: 1300: 1296: 1293: 1292: 1280: 1274: 1267: 1261: 1254: 1250: 1244: 1237: 1233: 1227: 1220: 1214: 1207: 1201: 1192: 1186: 1182: 1178: 1175: 1169: 1162: 1159: 1156: 1152: 1149: 1145: 1140: 1133: 1129: 1125: 1122: 1121:NaĂŻve Realism 1117: 1115: 1113: 1105: 1101: 1098: 1093: 1091: 1089: 1087: 1085: 1083: 1081: 1079: 1071: 1065: 1058: 1052: 1045: 1041: 1036: 1029: 1023: 1016: 1010: 1003: 999: 996: 990: 983: 979: 973: 966: 960: 953: 950: 944: 937: 933: 927: 920: 914: 907: 901: 894: 890: 885: 878: 874: 868: 861: 855: 848: 842: 835: 829: 822: 818: 815: 810: 808: 800: 794: 787: 781: 779: 771: 759: 755: 751: 747: 745:9781402082191 741: 737: 736: 728: 726: 709: 705: 701: 695: 686: 679: 675: 671: 668: 662: 655: 651: 647: 644: 638: 634: 623: 622: 618: 615: 612: 609: 606: 603: 600: 597: 594: 591: 588: 586: 585:Disjunctivism 583: 580: 577: 574: 571: 570: 564: 561: 554: 552: 548: 542: 540: 536: 525: 523: 518: 513: 509: 504: 498: 495: 494:Thomas Hobbes 490: 484: 482: 476: 474: 469: 464: 462: 452: 448: 446: 445: 440: 439: 433: 429: 425: 421: 411: 408: 403: 399: 395: 392: 386: 384: 383:hallucination 380: 372: 367: 363: 361: 357: 353: 352:echo-location 350:detectors or 349: 345: 341: 337: 333: 324: 310: 308: 304: 300: 296: 292: 288: 284: 280: 276: 272: 267: 265: 261: 257: 256:John McDowell 253: 252:Hilary Putnam 249: 245: 241: 236: 234: 230: 229:Gottlob Frege 226: 222: 218: 214: 210: 206: 204: 200: 196: 188: 184: 183: 182: 181:as follows: 180: 175: 173: 169: 168:G. W. Leibniz 165: 161: 157: 152: 150: 146: 142: 137: 135: 131: 130:object itself 127: 126: 121: 112: 108: 106: 102: 98: 94: 90: 85: 83: 79: 76:; out of the 75: 72: 68: 64: 60: 59:naĂŻve realism 56: 52: 48: 39: 33: 19: 1903: 1804:Common sense 1782:A posteriori 1781: 1773: 1744: 1735:Reductionism 1629: 1580:Gilbert Ryle 1450:Fred Dretske 1435:Keith DeRose 1379:Epistemology 1278: 1273: 1265: 1260: 1255:69:1, 48-54. 1252: 1248: 1243: 1235: 1231: 1226: 1218: 1213: 1205: 1200: 1191: 1184: 1168: 1160: 1157: 1139: 1069: 1064: 1056: 1051: 1043: 1035: 1027: 1022: 1014: 1009: 989: 981: 977: 972: 964: 959: 954:(9):445–518. 951: 948: 943: 935: 931: 926: 918: 913: 905: 900: 892: 889:Tom Rockmore 884: 876: 873:Tom Rockmore 867: 859: 854: 846: 841: 833: 828: 798: 793: 785: 768: 762:. Retrieved 734: 712:. Retrieved 708:the original 703: 694: 685: 677: 661: 653: 637: 620: 614:Subjectivism 556: 550: 546: 544: 534: 531: 516: 511: 507: 502: 499: 489:co-variation 488: 485: 477: 465: 457: 442: 438:res cogitans 436: 417: 404: 400: 396: 387: 376: 343: 329: 298: 294: 268: 237: 213:J. G. Fichte 207: 193: 176: 158:, including 153: 138: 123: 118: 109: 95:paradigm in 86: 84:experience. 78:metaphysical 66: 62: 58: 54: 44: 1884:Proposition 1854:Objectivity 1740:Reliabilism 1730:Rationalism 1675:Fallibilism 1650:Coherentism 1595:Ernest Sosa 1570:Thomas Reid 1555:James Pryor 1525:G. E. Moore 1515:David Lewis 1505:Saul Kripke 1500:Peter Klein 1480:Susan Haack 1410:Robert Audi 1158:Perception. 444:res extensa 432:rationalist 342:'s article 195:Thomas Reid 125:On the Soul 93:cognitivism 74:experiences 2000:Categories 1985:Discussion 1975:Task Force 1894:Simplicity 1874:Perception 1750:Skepticism 1725:Positivism 1700:Infinitism 1665:Empiricism 1520:John Locke 1485:David Hume 1475:Anil Gupta 1470:Paul Grice 1445:John Dewey 1415:A. J. Ayer 1148:Delusions. 982:Perception 764:2016-03-23 754:2008921236 629:References 590:Enactivism 560:elliptical 539:sense-data 508:to believe 424:homunculus 172:David Hume 164:John Locke 97:psychology 89:perception 1849:Knowledge 1834:Induction 1784:knowledge 1776:knowledge 1253:Analysis, 1249:Analysis, 573:Aspectism 520:known as 468:reference 358:like the 348:infra-red 179:qualities 120:Aristotle 82:conscious 71:conscious 1970:Category 1789:Analysis 1774:A priori 1765:Concepts 1705:Innatism 1642:Theories 1339:Archived 1321:Archived 1177:Archived 1151:Archived 1146:(2003). 1124:Archived 1100:Archived 998:Archived 980:Vol. 7, 875:(eds.), 817:Archived 758:Archived 670:Archived 646:Archived 567:See also 545:both an 461:inferred 371:Rainbows 332:Berkeley 307:idiolect 285:and the 105:idealism 63:indirect 1905:more... 1685:Fideism 1631:more... 1042:(1974) 714:Apr 27, 535:objects 481:dualism 428:regress 297:use of 295:private 223:in his 115:History 45:In the 1799:Belief 1695:Holism 752:  742:  551:object 299:public 277:) and 262:, and 225:Oxford 170:, and 55:direct 1980:Stubs 1899:Truth 1545:Plato 503:as if 273:(the 750:LCCN 740:ISBN 716:2022 377:The 336:1713 246:and 215:and 99:and 49:and 547:act 238:In 205:. 139:In 65:or 57:or 2002:: 1183:, 1161:32 1130:, 1111:^ 1077:^ 952:91 934:, 891:, 806:^ 777:^ 767:. 756:. 748:. 724:^ 702:. 676:, 652:, 524:. 266:. 258:, 254:, 211:, 174:. 166:, 162:, 151:. 143:, 53:, 1371:e 1364:t 1357:v 1134:. 718:. 680:. 656:. 334:( 34:. 20:)

Index

Indirect realism
Realism (visual arts)

philosophy of perception
philosophy of mind
conscious
experiences
metaphysical
conscious
perception
cognitivism
psychology
cognitive science
idealism
Aristotle
On the Soul
object itself
hylomorphic form
medieval philosophy
direct realism
Thomas Aquinas
early modern philosophers
René Descartes
John Locke
G. W. Leibniz
David Hume
qualities
Thomas Reid
Scottish common sense realism
Baruch Spinoza

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑